International Communist Party English language press


Elements of Marxist Economics
1929


- Manuscript, 1929
- Prometeo, 1947-1950
- Programme Communiste, 1958-1960
- Ed. Il Programma Comunista, 1971


Latest update on July 4, 2025
From the 1971 Presentation
1947 Introduction
Part I
Commo­dities
and Money
 1. The commodity
 2. Exchange value
 3. The simple form of value
 4. Total or expanded form of value
 5. Historical and social character of the question
 6. Circulation. Value and price
 7. The circulation of money
Part II
Transforma­tion of Money
into Capital
 8. From the circulation of money to the appearance of surplus-value
 9. Seeking the origin of surplus-value
10. The commodity “labor-power”
11. Purchase of “labor-power”
Part III
Surplus-value
12. Characteristic of labor in the capitalist era
13. The source of surplus-value
14. Summary of the demonstration
15. Constant capital and variable capital
16. Rate of surplus-value
17. General law of surplus-value
18. Demonstration of the fundamental law
19. Representation of the value of the product into proportional parts of the quantities of the product or the working day
20. Appendix - calculation of the enterprise referred to in paragraph 18.
21. Duration of the working day
22. Plus-labor and capitalism
23. Capital and surplus-value
Part IV
Capitalism and Empower­ment
of Labor
24. Relative surplus-value
25. Collaboration
26. Manufacturing
27. Machinery
28. Replacement of machines for workers
29. Other characteristic of mechanisms
30. Large-scale industry and agriculture
31. Historical events in the production of surplus-value. Evolution of economic science
Part V
Absolute
and Relative
Surplus-value
32. Distribution of the value produced by labor between the capitalist and the wage‑earner
Part VI
The Wage
33. General law of surplus‑value
Part VII
The
Accumu­lation
of Capital
34. Reproduction of capital
35. Simple reproduction
36. Progressive reproduction
37. Variations in the magnitude of accumulation
38. Theory of the alleged wage fund
39. General law of capitalist accumulation
40. Change in the composition of the capital - Concentration - Centralization
41. Redundancy of working-class population or “industrial reserve army”
42. Forms of the redundancy of the working-class population
Part VIII
Original
or Primitive
Accumu­lation
43. Historical forms of ownership and the origins of capital
44. Conditions for the formation of capitalism
45. The expropriation of the peasants
46. Fight for the “liberation” of the workers
47. Genesis of the agrarian capitalist
48. Genesis of industrial production
49. Genesis of the industrial capitalist
50. Factors of original (or primitive) accumulation
51. The theory of modern colonization
Conclusion 52. The historical outlet of capitalist accumulation
53. What will be the further development of capitalism
54. New contrast between productive forces and forms of property - The proletarian revolution
Index of K.Marx Capital


Adopted Symbols

Commodity   G
Money   M
Advanced Capital C+V K
Final Capital C+V+S K’
Constant Capital A+B+H C
Variable Capital wgv V
Surpuls-Value ez S
Rent   R
Interest   I
Value of product   F
Depreciation rate   A
Raw Materials   B
Auxiliary Materials   H
Market Price   P
Rate of Surplus-value S/V s
Rate of Profit S/(C+V) p
Interest Rate I/(C+V) i
Organic Composition C/V o
Labor Time n+e t
Necessary Labor   n
Surplus-Labor   e
Production of value per hour   z
Added unitary price   f
Mean work productivity   m
Daily product   L
Number of workers   w
Annual number of working days   g
One hour wage   v





[From the 1971 Presentation]

The Elements of Marxist Economics was originally composed in Ponza in 1929. It was in these years, despite our defeat at Lyon and shortly afterwards at the VI Enlarged Executive of the Communist International in 1926, that our current, in emigration or confinement, in prison or in solitude, nevertheless supported the last and vehement battle in defense of the Marxist doctrine and program against all mystification. Since then is it our characteristic, repeated a thousand times in this text, that Marxism is a unique and invariant block which cannot be reduced to a simple “method” of interpreting facts as they happen. Rather, it offers a global vision of the course of human history and the very becoming of nature; it is not a mosaic of which one can change the tesserae at will, leaving the overall picture unchanged, but a scientific and global conception of the world in which everything is linked, and no one can willingly accept or reject any seperate part at will without disfiguring it and thus destroying its revolutionary power.

The text, in its original form, was intended “in a certain way to sort out and align the economic part” of Capital but from all its pages, as from those of Marx’s cyclopean work, both the battle cry of the working class fighting for the overthrow of the bourgeois mode of production, whose infamies hidden behind a democratic screen and its State superstructure are denounced, is the anticipated vision of society in which mankind will finally emerge from its prehistory and, ideally rejoining the beginnings of an associated community life, will base all relations of production and human coexistence on criteria that are not mercantile, not individualistic, not vulgarly contingent, but finally human and rational.

So it’s all economics, “philosophy”, politics: in short, class warfare.









Elements of Marxist Economics


1947 Introduction

[Prometeo, No. 5, January‑February 1947]
[Programme Communiste, n. 2, 1958]

The work we take to publish is an exposition, in a somewhat different form from the original, of the First Book of Capital. It is not a summary and much less a vulgarisation. The study of Marx’s fundamental work requires a historical and philosophical economic preparation whose results must be applied in parallel. Here, the economic part of the text is in a certain way thinned out and aligned.

A similar work for the historical and philosophical part can give sufficient basis to the work for a correct approach and knowledge of the integral doctrine of communism, in its classic original enunciation.







[Prometeo, n. 6, March‑April 1947]

The first part of this study corresponds to the First Section of the First Book entitled by the author Commodities and Money.

For the Practical purpose of establishing a new numbering, we will consider the study divided into the seven following points:

1. Definition of the commodity and its two properties: value in use and exchange value.

2. Exchange value. The quantitative concept and difficulty in finding the measure.

3. The simple form of value. Whenever we talk about value, we will henceforth refer to exchange value. The simple form is the statement of equivalence, for the purpose of exchange, between two goods which are both susceptible to use (consumption), so that a given quantity of commodity A corresponds to a given quantity of commodity B.

4. General form of value and equivalent form. It occurs when we consider a given number of different goods and we know all the equivalences between pairs of them. With two goods we have two equivalence, the simple form. With three goods we have six equivalences, with four twelve. With ten goods we would have ninety equivalences, a system too complicated for practical and mnemonic purposes. To remember the ninety relationships it is enough to know those of nine goods with only one and therefore only nine relationships from which the others easily derive. One commodity has been chosen as the equivalent of all. We are at the general form of value.

5. Historical-social character of the whole question. We have briefly summarized a chapter, the one on “The fetishism of commodities and the secret thereof” that summarizes all the elements of the Marxist doctrine in a masterful foreshortening, on the economic, historical and philosophical side together. We have reported just enough to clarify that Marxist economics does not go into the subtleties in the analysis of commodities to find immanent and immutable laws of the economic process (the claimed natural laws of economics) but – in order to expose with rigorous development the scientific investigation on the becoming of human society in all its complexity and in the historical succession of its events – referred to different eras from a different mechanics of the economic world. It therefore investigates not the relationship between the piece of cloth and the iron pound, but the relationship between real men in production and consumption to data carried out in history.

6. Circulation. Value and price. At this point the market as a whole is studied, when a commodity chosen as a general equivalent, such as salt, is finally replaced by currency, first metallic and then also paper and conventional. In this development is put in front of the hypothesis that in order to have a measure of the value we can adopt the one of the average human working time that every goods requires in general to be produced. The progressive application of this hypothesis (which, as is known, is not found for the first time in Marx but is due to the economists of the first capitalist era and in particular to David Ricardo (1772‑1823) who published his fundamental work, Principles of Political Economics, in London in 1821) to the whole economic world present in the development of research will decide on the validity of the hypothesis itself.

7. Path of the money. The Second Section, where Capital finally comes onto the scene, deals precisely with the transformation of money into capital – investigated by studying the dynamics no longer of those who enter the market to bring goods or withdraw them for their own use, but of those who descend as bearers of money. As a premise Marx recalls how much it is necessary to establish regarding the essential monetary mechanism in the bourgeois economy, before continuing with the exposition of all “the process of capitalist production”, the theme of the First Book of the work.

* * *

Having said this as a prologue to the First Section of the First Book, it will be good to give some indication of the partition of the whole work, which in Marx’s plan was to include four Books or Volumes. Of them only the First is known in full in Italian, while the Fourth could not have be written by Marx.

The Second Book deals with the process of the circulation of Capital, the third of the aspects that cover the overall economic process; the Fourth was to expose the history of theory, of which, however, there are copious materials in the first Books and their annotations.

Among the many Prometeo tasks may be that of an exposition of the two subsequent Books of Capital, much less known than the First.

It is good, however, to remove a current convention and much used for revisionist purposes,that is, that the two subsequent Books examine a part of the real economic process that was omitted in the First, and that this analysis was carried out by the author to the point of leading him to important corrections if not to renunciations of the main doctrines of the First Book such as those of surplus-value, the accumulation of capital, the growing misery, etc. This opinion, contradicted by the context of even the most recent works that appeared until Marx’s death (1883) and afterwards, as by the posthumous reworking and exegesis by Engels, corresponds to an erroneous evaluation of the constructive framework of the work. The First Book covers the complete field of Marx’s doctrine on capitalism and is certainly not an abstract treatment of relations that are established in the sphere of production and that prescind from the relations of the circulation of goods and currency. To believe this would be to consider the substantial content of Marx’s method destroyed.

What defines the relationship between the First Book of Capital and the rest of the Work is an entirely different criterion. As rich as it is in historical, critical, bibliographic and polemical material, the First Book carries out the economic study of the whole process, from the first exchange to barter on through the birth and accumulation of capital to the conclusion that capitalism will be succeeded by a social economy and not a mercantile one, traced out lapidarily in the penultimate chapter, as we shall see at the appropriate time. The data, the study and the laws of circulation are already fully understood in this development. But all the material is taken up and re‑examined in the following books – and, explaining the concept better, we can well say in all the later and also future work of Marxists – by way of study of the particular phenomena of capitalist development, from which, given the character of the method, the verification and control of the general theory and the proof of its efficiency must incessantly be drawn.

The First Book therefore gives us the essential development of the capitalist process and its real social characteristics in the relationship between capitalist and wage‑earners, which is impractical and unimaginable without taking into account the phenomena of circulation and consumption, and finds the laws of this process, although not crystallizing them in the statics of an abstract world but verifying them in all situations: of nascent capitalism and put in relation with different economic types, and then in the course of its development and its conquest of the world. Therefore, it always takes into account the real historical environment, since it can never be said to be in the presence of a “model” of capitalist economy in the “pure” state.

And, in fact, the famous First Section of the First Book, on circulation, is the cornerstone on which the whole study of production rests, and because of the well‑known warnings of Marx himself and of the best commentators it is the most difficult, especially for readers who are not well prepared, even though its comprehension is completely indispensable to the whole.

But it has also been said many times that a work like Marx’s, from which every apriorism and every metaphysics of principles have been expelled, must be acquired in all its parts, and reading the first chapters presupposes a certain assimilation of the theses of the following parts. Marx himself suggested to some readers to start halfway through the book from the descriptive and historical chapters and then to the decisive ones of scientific analysis.

The First Book therefore stands for everything else as the fundamental trace, the guideline of the whole system, which has its own completeness and complete cycle, and was written by the author on the basis of all the materials that economic history up to its time offered him, and of which he reserved detailed exposure to the following volumes.

It holds the place that in modern physics and astronomy hold the Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica by Isaac Newton (1687). Of a single jet, from the truth due to Galileo that the force acting on a material body in motion is the cause not of its speed but of its acceleration (i.e. it increases or decreases the speed itself), the mathematical procedure, with the methods of calculation of the very small quantities found by Newton, leads directly to establish the laws of motion of a planet around the sun and finds deductively the laws that Kepler had inferred from Tycho Brahe’s observations on planetary revolutions. The theoretical principle thus receives dazzling confirmation. It is worth noting that even the first part of Newton’s work, which establishes in geometric form the first propositions of infinitesimal calculus, found at the same time by Leibniz in another more expressive form, is hard to study and boring, while the deduction of the following chapters in which the famous law of universal gravitation is great and brilliant even in form.

The three or four very simple statements by Galileo, Newton, Kepler give full reason for all the motions of the bodies of the solar system, planets and satellites, and have definitive value in the history of science. This does not detract from the fact that they derive from a pure and abstract case, that of central motion, which considers only two celestial bodies, while in the system there are a great number of them. The real effect is therefore very complicated. Already the problem of the three bodies appears, analytically, much more difficult. Yet admitted the Newton’s famous action at a distance, each body attracts each other and deforms its trajectory more or less. Something similar to the passage from Marx’s simple G → G’ barter to the general picture of today’s economic movement. To the following volumes of Capital we will therefore compare the gigantic later work performed by astronomers in deducing the particular motions of the various bodies, and especially the fundamental and classical Mécanique Céleste by Laplace, the famous applications such as the discovery of Neptune made by Le Verrier by calculating the perturbations of Saturn’s orbit, identifying its precise position in the sky, then verified by observation through the telescope.

The same theory therefore regulates the study of many effective deviations of detail from the standard law and the pure Keplerian ellipses, but Newton’s law remains solidly established and reconfirmed. The standard process is absolutely valid and yet it never happens. Not only are the heavens no longer immutable and incorruptible as they were for Aristotle and Thomas, and they are rectified by the same valid mechanics for the motion of the grave earths studied by Galileo, but Kepler’s geometrically exquisite orbits are not immutable traces to the motion of the planets. Each of them never traces them twice, the real phenomenon is always different from the theoretical one, but this only confirms the validity and effectiveness of the scientific law.

Introduced further considerations on thermal processes it becomes possible to attempt a history of the solar system and Laplace puts forward his hypothesis on the origin of the planets from the sun and their future fallout into it. This, of course, does not take away the validity of the scientific conquest contained in the first classical construction of the general law of motion.

To avoid confusion, not always innocent, we mention one last point. The methodological issues mentioned here are not affected, in the development of the comparison with the cosmogonic problem, by recent acquisitions and scientific doctrines that introduce in the balance in addition to the thermal considerations those of atomic energy, nor by broader constructions such as those of relativistic theory that have not denied (in the sense that interests us here) the classical law of gravitation, but have framed it in a broader conception as a “limit case”. All this, like the question of determinism in the science of nature and in the science of man, must be reserved for further studies such as those on Marxism and theory of knowledge.

* * *

The notes we are publishing serve as an introduction to the reading of Capital, and even better to the political work with the handling of that fundamental and revolutionary instrument. A book is for us like a machine; more, like a weapon.

It would be useful, since any work of investigation is nowadays for us socialists collective and not personal, for the illumination of the text by already prepared militants.

For example, the fourth paragraph of the first chapter on the fetish character of the commodity contains very topical propaganda material on points that the opportunists of the moment put under their feet at least three times a day, while they claim to be students of Marx

In a few pages it provides a historical glimpse of the various economies whose use of the dialectical method we will discuss in our course extensively, it is shown that not all past economies were mercantile, and that the socialist economy is defined, as a first condition, by being non‑commercial and non‑monetary. The thesis is contained that any apologetics of capitalism in economics and of equality and freedom in politics, tending to contrast the perfection and dignity of bourgeois institutions with the “artificiality” of feudal ones, is scientifically worth as little as the position of all theologians, according to whom the religions of others are artificial, theirs alone is natural. Any religion that is not theirs is an invention of men, theirs is the revelation of God. Marx quotes himself here in his answer to Proudhon on the Misery of Philosophy. For us Marxists all religions are “inventions” of men.

Today, under the incredible label of Marxism, from Attlee to Stalin, from Saragat to Togliatti, of all the nuances that fit in, under the incredible label of Marxism, no one is beating mercantilism or deism. They all feel they are going in an anti‑capitalistic sense without bothering the commodity fetish, the “beast” (it is Marx who quotes the Apocalypse of John) currency, nor the god of the altars.

None of them remember reading:

     «The religious world is but a reflection of the real world. A society in which the product of labour generally takes the form of a commodity; where consequently the most common relationship between producers consists in buying the values of their products and, in this simple form, in comparing their private work with each other as equal human labour (these characteristics remain intact in the statizations of both Labour and Russian totalitarianism); such a society finds in Christianity with its cult of abstract man, and especially in its bourgeois development, Protestantism, deism, etc., the most appropriate form of religion.
     «In general, the religious reflection of the real world can only disappear because the conditions of work and practical life will present man with clear and reasonable relations with his fellow human beings and with nature.
     «Social life, of which material production and the relationships it implies form the basis, will not tear the mystical veil of fog that hides its appearance except on the day when the work of men freely associated, consciously acting according to a determined plan and masters of their own social movement, will manifest itself. But this requires a material basis of society or a set of conditions of material existence, which in turn are but the product of a long and painful historical development».

But now, in order not to frighten the allies of the fideist movements, the “Marxists” no longer speak of these problems. Their followers are made to believe that silence is only a temporary skillful maneuver.

At most they say that Lenin quotes from Marx that religion is the opium of the people: a phrase of passage in which the terms are not in the light of theoretical rigor. Do we need a passage from Lenin, to avoid they say that we are the ones who invent a Marx and a Lenin in our own way? Here it is:

«We materialists, after Engles, term the Kantians and Humeans agnostics, because they deny the objective reality of the source of our sensations. The agnostics says: I do not know if there is an objective reality, reflected, represented by our sensations; I declare it impossible to know. Hence the denial of objective truth the agnostic and a tolerance −a bourgeois, philistine, cowardly tolerance− of the dogmas of house goblins and wood demons, Catholic saints and the like»
(Materialism and Empirio criticsm, Chap II, par. 4).

The allusion to werewolves and spirits comes from a polemic with the self‑styled Russian Marxist Bagdanov who, embracing the philosophy fashionable in 1910 of Mach & Avenarius, however, claimed the anti‑fideist position. Lenin contests this and among other things says «If truth (including scientific truth) is but an organizing form of human experience, then the fundamental postulate of clericalism is admitted, the door remains open to it, and room is made for the “organizing forms” of religious experience».

Where we see that for the Marxist the terms fideism, clericalism, religion Christianity and deism, are equal expressions of an enemy thesis, and that the same heterodox as Bogdanov were until yesterday ashamed to have a tolerance for them.

But today, a duly purged edition of Marx and Lenin is expected. While you’re at it, couldn’t you include the formation of the commission in the Lateran Pacts?

 

 

 

 

 



[Prometeo, n.5, January‑February 1947]


Part I - COMMODITIES AND MONEY

1. The commodity

A commodity is an object which possesses two properties: a) being useful, that is able to satisfy human needs; b) and susceptible to exchange with other commodities.

We use the term use‑value to describe this property a). Does it correspond to a measurable quantity? No, because use‑value of even the same commodity varies according to the circumstances of time, place and person. Use‑value is therefore a qualitative property that cannot be treated as a quantitative magnitude (1).

Exchange-value: We thus designate the second property of the commodity, that is, its exchangability.

Is exchange value quantitatively measurable? And if so, to what known quantities must it be attributed to? We answer the first question in the affirmative because, although at first sight a given commodity allows for many isolated exchanges for various quantities of other commodities, in all these relations there must be something in common.

As for the second question, we cannot ascribe a measure of exchange value to the specific properties that define use‑value, such as color, flavor, shape, chemical composition, etc., because the commodity can be exchanged for other commodities of any use‑value without changing its exchange value. The common character of various commodities that can be exchanged indiscriminately can only be reduced to the fact that they are all products of human labor.


2. Exchange value

We then propose to measure exchange value by referring to labor, a common measurable quantity. Human labor is only measurable as labor time.

It must be immediately understood that it is not a matter of the time of work occasionally required to produce a given commodity, which can vary under a thousand circumstances, but of the average time of work required to reproduce it systematically, i.e. socially necessary labor time

Exchange value is the ability of a commodity to be exchanged with others in a given relationship, and is a measurable quantity.

The number which will measure exchange value with respect to an agreed unit of measurement is always proportional to the social-average labor time required to produce a given commodity, i.e. the number itself is given by this time divided by the labor time required to produce the agreed unit of the exchange value.

The productive power of average labor varies if the processes of technology vary. When this happens, the exchange value of goods of that type varies. Of course, it also varies for the goods still existing, produced with the unimproved system and with a longer working time.

Hence it can be seen that the formula that value is crystallized labor is also erroneous and it is necessary to formulate the law in the precise terms stated above.

Labor is represented in a dual form within the commodity: use value is in relation to the particular quality of the labor required; the exchange value is in relation to the quantity of average human labor time is required to reproduce it.

When we speak of time and labor power, we are referring to simple labor, from which complex or qualified labor must be distinguished. Throughout this discussion, complex labor is always reduced to simple labor, as we will see later.


3. The simple form of value

[Programme Communiste, n. 10, 1960]

A commodity has two forms: its natural form, most often physical and material, and its value form.

And in which form does value appear to us? In practice, as experimental data, value appears to us in the form of money, which is basically the price. It is a matter of arriving at this practical data, familiar to all, by a deductive analysis that starts from the simple property of exchange that all goods possess, since we have established that they have a value (of exchange) insofar as they can be exchanged.

Let’s start from the simplest fact of the exchange between two lots of commodities:


x commodity A  =  y commodity B

The form of value appears here at first in a way we can describe as simple or particular. We then have an equality, with two members. Although we can, as in any quantitative equality, change their places, nevertheless the expressions x Commodity A and y Commodity B have a different character. They express the same quantities of value; but y Commodity B is used to define how much Commodity A is worth. So we will call the first member the relative form, and the second the equivalent form.


Simple form of value:
Value of x commodity A  =  Value of y commodity B  =  Value V
Relative Form Equivalent Form

If we wanted to express the absolute magnitude of the value V by a number, that is to say, to express it according to a general unit of measurement, applicable to all goods A, B, C, D, etc. we could not do so starting from the data of the simple formula. We can in fact deduce from this relation:
Value of x commodity A  =  Value of y commodity B  =  Value V

But this does not allow us to say what is the magnitude of a unit (Kg, etc.) of A, because it depends on the value of B. Moreover the value of A, as well as that of B, can change as a result of variations in the time of the work necessary for A or B; in this case the ratio will change, and we will thus have various expressions of the value sought, i.e. we will not have yet arrived at an absolute measure.


4. Total or expanded value form

With the simple form, the commodity of interest to us finds only one equivalent, and we do not arrive at a general measure of value. Taking a step further, suppose we know all the equivalents of commodity A expressed by the other commodities on the market.

Value of x
goods A
 =  Value of y
goods B
 =  Value of z
goods C
 =  etc...
etc...
 =  Value V

To have an idea of the whole market (we think of the time of barter) we must know how to write for each commodity the developed form indicated above. If there are n goods, this one consists of n‑1 equalities, and in all there are n(n‑1) equalities. For example, for 10 goods we must know 90 relations.

The n(n‑1) or 90 relations are not all independent, however, and are all contained in the n‑1 or 9 of the developed form. We then only have to reverse the latter and to refer the value of all the other n‑1 goods to that of the commodity A, which has become the unique equivalent or general equivalent. We will have:


y commodity B = commodity C = commodity D etc. = commodity A

In practice this means that, as bartering has become widespread, in order not to have to remember 90 relationships, one commodity has been elevated to the rank of common equivalent of all others.

We do not yet have an absolute expression of the measure or quantity of value, but we do have a measure of it, as it were, expressed by the quantity of the equivalent commodity which corresponds to each special commodity. Thus the savages, for example, trade in cattle by expressing their value in pounds of salt.

With the development of trade the equivalent commodity fulfills not only a mnemonic function, but is in fact exchanged for all other commodities, the direct contact between the individual exchangers having disappeared. The simple form (for example: 1 cow = 3 goats) is no longer realized, but we have the exchange between a cow and 30 pounds of salt, then between 10 pounds of salt and a goat. Or the trader interposes himself between the one who sells the cow and the one who sells the goat, because they can both be materially distant; the trader carries the merchandise or the salt equivalent to bring everyone together. The salt no longer circulates only to be consumed, but much more frequently to facilitate the circulation of other goods.

It is necessary, however, that the equivalent commodity be easy to transport, not very bulky, absolutely unalterable. These qualities are combined in gold, which has become the general equivalent: and so we pass to the form of value.


5. Historical and social character of the question

Having reached this stage of the analysis of value, Marx inserts a chapter on “the fetish character of the commodity and its secret”. This chapter has a historical and polemical character and it presupposes an enunciation of the doctrine of economic determinism that does not enter into the object of Capital, but is inseparable from the Marxist doctrine on the character of the Marxist economics.

This chapter is not a digression, and it is not the intention here to give a summary of it, whereas it should rather be given the widest development.

In analyzing the forms of value, we applied the positive scientific method to the question. But the object of our research was not facts of absolute and immanent character, as for example the nature of chemical elements – discovered in 1800, but valid also for discussing the conditions of the original nebula as well as those of the distant future of the universe. We had to go into the historical field to explain the stages of our research, linking the simple form of value to the time of barter in kind, the general form and to that of trade, etc... Thus the results to which we tend do not have an immanent character, but are relative to the various times and degrees of development of the society.

Recognizing labor time as the measure of quantities of value is not enough without an analysis that applies this key to various economies.

What is acquired for the first time by Marxist research is that exchange value is not an absolute property of things, but the reflection of the relations of social organization. Objects are commodities because there is a certain system of relations between the people who produce and consume them. Moreover, it is natural that the economists who preceded us should see in the commodity a primary datum, because they take for definitive and natural relations those which correspond to the society in which they live and to the interests of the classes they represent. Marx develops here our doctrine, which makes opinions depend on the stage of development of the social economy and on the class struggle.

Above all, the polemic against the traditional economists does not take place on ground that is common to any of them, and they play the role of passive objects of research, rather than collaborators – or even adversaries. We are not concerned with what they may allege later, even for a very long time to come: in the same way the founders of modern mechanics and astronomy do not consider biblical and peripatetic developments as working material. If one does not understand this, it is useless to hope to understand how the analysis, starting from the minimal fact of the permutation of two objects, arrives at the doctrine of surplus-value which must provide the key to the positive and historical interpretation of the contemporary productive mechanism.

We therefore strip the commodity of its fetish character by discovering the laws that assign it a value and provide us with the means to measure it in the relations between men and groups of men for whom commodities and values are involved.

(Chapter II, “the process of exchange”, is implicitly summarized in the historical considerations indicated in parallel to the passage from the simple form to the money form).


6. Circulation - Value and price

We have tried to consider value as a measurable quantity, in order to treat it by the scientific method and to discover the laws relative to it. We have assumed that the quantitative value is proportional to the average social work time. By analyzing the experimental facts, we applied and verified the hypothesis. We have reached the general equivalent commodity and a new step forward has brought us to money.

We leave aside the observations on mono or bi‑metallism.

Gold by its quantity and weight, expressed in the monetary terminology, indicates therefore with a certain unit to measure the value of goods.

In conclusion we have reduced the measure we are looking for to the value of gold, that is, according to our hypothesis, to the time of work necessary to produce the gold. So the term of comparison is variable, and therefore general oscillations can occur, which are easy to interpret.

The price expresses the ratio between the value of the commodity considered and the value of the gold unit (for example, according to the original ratio: one pound = sterling). Or, which is the same thing, the price, according to us, expresses the ratio between the labor time needed for the commodity and the labor time needed for the pound of gold.

When we talk about the necessary working time, we want to distinguish it from the working time that was actually required in a specific case; this time can be higher or lower as a result of mistakes or, on the contrary, of the producer’s manufacturing secrets. In addition, due to other considerations, the price can express more or less than the abstract value of the merchandise, because of exceptional circumstances of the alienation.

If, for example, while using the necessary average time, all the producers provide a given market with a quantity of the commodity X exceeding the consumption, let’s say of 20%, as a result of an error in the social division of labor, this 20% will be lost. And this can also manifest itself in the form of a temporary fall in price below value, with each producer discounting 20% of his working time, as in the case where, as a result of clumsiness, he has used 6 hours instead of 5. The opposite case can also occur, that is, a rise in price above value.

This case should not be confused with that of a fall in price as a consequence of new technical inventions which reduce the necessary working time; for in this case it is the value itself which has fallen and which will not rise again. In the previous cases, known phenomena, provoking the opening of new enterprises or the closing of old ones, tend to level the prices.

(The winning horse of the Derby has a very high price because among 20 competing horses, which have absorbed equal care (working time), only one can win this price. The profit of one breeder compensates for the losses of the other 19, but this does not prevent the relationship between the value of a horse and the amount of work absorbed by its breeding. It is only a question of a production that, for technical reasons, does not give a series of equal objects, but products that are very different due to unforeseeable circumstances at the beginning of the enterprise).

We can therefore speak of a quantity of value which does not necessarily coincide with the price form, but which is its basis, since the price can oscillate above and below the value. An opportune research will succeed in determining it.

In the same way, in the physical sciences, it is difficult to establish at first sight the mass of a given body, of a wooden ball for example. We feel that it tends to fall, and we measure its weight: but it varies according to whether we are at the pole or at the equator, at sea level or in the mountains, and finally it even becomes negative if we immerse the ball in water. This does not prevent the constant quantity of mass from being measurable, and from being used to formulate the laws that will elucidate all these variations of weight, which previously appeared as an arena of contradictory data. A later refinement of the scientific results, which establishes that the mass of a body in motion varies at the same time as its speed, does not prevent that it is rightly introduced and treated this quantity in the field of the phenomena considered in the research.

The science of mechanics was born when mass was measured, a datum which, in a certain sense, is neither concrete nor sensible; the science of economics was born with the measurement of the quantity value, whereas it is not a scientific work if one claims to have to limit oneself to knowing and recording contingent prices, under the pretext that it is only these that are measured and expressed in figures.

Let us now continue the analysis of the market by examining the path followed by the commodity. The possessor brings it to the market, sells it for a certain amount of money, which is not for his own use, but only to buy another commodity. The cycle is:


Commodity → Money → Commodity

G → M → G

The second part of this cycle (MG) is, for the owner of the other commodity, the first part (GM) of another cycle and so on, indefinitely. The set of all these cycles, each of which has a common half with another, represents the circulation, according to the diagram:


G1MG2MG3MG4 → etc.



7. The circulation of money

In the movement of the circulation of goods, money passes in its turn from hand to hand; but while each commodity arrives on the market from the outside to leave it immediately, money on the contrary remains constantly there.

It is obviously not necessary for the money in circulation to be equal to the sum of the prices of all the individual “buy‑sells”; on the contrary, since each gold fragment circulates several times, a smaller sum is sufficient. The quotient of the sum of all prices (business figures) in a given time by the mass of money available is called the speed of circulation in that time.

It is worth noting, with regard to money, the transition from the form in which pure gold is used to the form of gold money – the weight of which may be less than the theoretical value – then to coins of silver and non‑noble metals with a partly conventional value, and finally to paper money, the value of which is purely figurative: all forms which, under normal conditions, do not alter in any way the circulation relations between money and goods.

Money can, moreover, assume other functions, besides those of measuring the value of goods or serving as a vehicle for their exchange. These forms are: hoarding or accumulation; deposit to meet payments in advance or delayed in relation to the moment when the merchandise changes owner (the game of debit and credit); universal currency or element of compensation in exchanges between nations, for which gold transfers compensate for the imbalances in trade balances, gold being, in this sense, the only currency that is effectively valid throughout the world. Today, something that did not exist in Marx’s time, it is not only gold that is capable of assuming a worldwide validity, but also a paper currency: the dollar, which circulates without being exchanged against other national currencies.

The detailed study of these economic phenomena is not necessary before proceeding to the study of the transformation of money into capital, which is the starting point of the laws of circulation that bring into play the commodity and money.

 

 

 

 

 



[Prometeo, n. 6, marzo‑aprile 1947]


Part II - THE TRANSFORMATION OF MONEY INTO CAPITAL


8. From the circulation of money to the appearance of surplus-value

The formula for the circulation of money and commodities is thus G → M → G. If we consider the person who brings commodities to exchange them for others of different use values while having the same quantity of (exchange) value, except for secondary circumstances. For this person, money is only an indication of value and a vehicle of exchange. But in the whole mercantile system, currency immediately introduces new relations and new actors, whose intervention makes the exchange of use values possible for others. They use money and with it they buy goods which they resell for more money. Circulation, from this second point of view, is represented by the formula M → G → M. The intervention of this second group of actors cannot be explained without a motive.

This is not a quest for use values, since their money eventually returns to money, without qualitative change. Therefore there can be no purpose and motive except in a quantitative change. While in the case of G → M → G, the movement of a constant value is explained. This is no longer the case for M → G → M, if the amount of money remained the same after purchase and sale. Philanthropy or other ideal forces cannot be the incentive for the bearers of money, this is determined by the fact that in general the amount of money the second time is greater than the first time. The formula therefore becomes M → G → M’, where M’ = M + ΔM. The original amount of money, M, is increased by an increment ΔM (Delta M). This increase is called surplus-value.

For the money bearer the movement of money in exchange serves as production of surplus-value, which is immediately added to the per‑existing value and returns to the cycle to increase yet again.

It is in this way that money, from simple representation of value and vehicle of exchange, neccesarialy becomes capital.

Capital is value whose peculiarity is to increase continuously.

A mercantile system, once past the stage of bartering in kind, must blossom into capitalism.

In this definition, summarized in the formula M → G → M’, only commercial capital would seem to be considered. That is, all the goods which stay in possession of the professional money bearers of the market, who offer goods purchased from producers.

But even for industrial capital there is money which is transformed into commodities only to return to money with the sale of the latter, this will be the subject of further discussion.

Marx at the beginning of this Section establishes – in a fundamental historical reference that accompany the illustrative exposition of the capitalist process – that «capital appears only where production and the circulation of goods, or trade, have reached a certain development. The modern history of capital dates from the creation of trade and the world market in the sixteenth century».

The pure form M → M’ then represents usury, in which there is no passage through a commodity. Usury is meant in the sense of any arrangement of money for interest.

In M → M it is possible to reduce the formula to hording, which removes money from circulation. In doing so this takes away money’s possibility to generate surplus-value, and thus is not yet in the form of capital.


9. Seeking the origin of surplus‑value

Surplus-value, the increase (ΔM) in the amount M underwent to become M’, can not and will never be explained in the field of circulation alone.

All attempts made in this sense fail before the elementary fact that circulation consists of a series of exchanges between equivalents.

One can point to many exceptions to this law, but they are not worth expounding on, when the increase from M to M’ occurs with confirmable regularity.

If one ascribes to buying the virtue of bringing about an imbalance in favor of the money‑bearer, or such virtue is ascribed to selling, since both in the simple circuit M → G → M, and in the whole of circulation each interested party appears as many times a seller and buyer, the supposed differences offset each other in a general equality. The same is true if all prices went up or down together.

The explanation that the one who buys in order to consume pays more than the one who sells having made a product does not hold up either. As the consumer draws his money from the fact of having been in turn a producer. Therefore we should suppose consumers who draw value from something other than productive work, i.e. not through exchange. Such a class will therefore receive money, not through circulation, but by extorting, in the material sense of the term, the merchandise or money belonging to others. This explanation is inadequate for the mercantile age.

It is not even worth mentioning exceptionally disproportionate or even fraudulent buying and selling, because this explains the transfer of special values from one hand to another, rather than the formation of the smallest part of surplus-value.

We insert a parenthesis to show that not even the syndicate or even monopoly regime of producers can explain the normal genesis of surplus-value in the circulation sphere. If in the ordinary mercantile regime of free competition the producer of commodity A was free to raise their price, they would have realized a surplus-value. But this can never happen, because it is obvious that buyers would abandon them and turn to other sellers of the same commodity, so that this mechanism, except for secondary phenomena, maintains all prices at a minimum level corresponding to exchange value. Now, we could suppose that all or some of the producers of commodity A agree to raise its price arbitrarily; the game of competition would be eliminated and a surplus-value resulting purely and simply from circulation would be realized.

To such an objection one may reply that if, in the analysis, we wanted to substitute for the general and typical system of free competition, a stable system of monopolies – and not an intermediate system which will always remain to be examined, but which serves for the application and not for the research of general laws – we would then be led to consider that all the groups of producers have constituted themselves into monopolies, and sell each other commodities at overvalued prices but which find a new equilibrium by compensation. We would thus find ourselves back at the same point. The monopolization agreements will have achieved, in an intermediate stage, an appropriation of value on the backs of the lagging monopolists, but they will not have been able to produce surplus-value.

In conclusion, the problem reduces down to these seemingly contradictory terms: In circulation, exchanges take place only between equivalents; money circulating as capital leaves circulation having undergone an increase.

In pursuit of the solution, do not lose sight of the fact that for a capitalist economic society in a stable and normal set‑up both statements have systematic value, that is, they are realized in the vast majority of cases, so that citing particular cases and moments of instability cannot serve to evade the need to give an equally general solution to the “system of equations” that we can write:

     Value of M = value of G
     Value of G = value of M’
     Value of M’ is larger than the value of M .

We shall see why the equations are not incompatible, as would be found if we gave them a purely arithmetical sense – or, in other words, why this patently contradiction to the formal rules of logical syllogism (a contradiction which, as Marx recalls, Aristotle discerned but could not explain, nor could he with the data of his time explain) is implemented in the reality of economic life, since in this, Capital is generated.


10. The commodity “labor power”

At what stage of the process can the increase in value have originated? It cannot come from money from itself since a quantity of money remains materially unchanged. Therefore, the increase arises from the exchange of money for commodity. It cannot arise from the second act G → M’ just as it cannot arise from the first M → G, if these are exchanges between equivalents.

Marx’s fundamental discovery is this: the increase in value cannot arise from the two exchanges; it arises, rather, from the use of the commodity, since there exists in the market a commodity whose use coincides with a systematic increase in its exchange value.

If the use of a commodity produces value, and if value corresponds to the availability of labor time, the mysterious commodity in question must be such as to make human labor available: that commodity is precisely labor, or, more accurately, labor power.

Under certain historical conditions, while those who buy any commodity generally resell it for the same amount of money (value), those who buy labor power pay for it at a certain amount while systematically reselling it for a higher amount. What the buyer of labor power resells are actually material goods to which has undergone transformations by applying purchased labor power to them. This is the case when the worker, or owner of labor power, because of legal and social conditions cannot make contact with the commodity to be transformed (raw material). Either because he does not possess money, and therefore cannot anticipate the value of the raw material itself; or the transformation of labor requires technical means (tools of labor, concentration of large numbers of workers) which are the monopoly of others (of the owners of money or capital).

There is another condition: namely, that the worker is free, for he must remain in possession of his own labor power in order to sell it in portions (periods of time). Should he be able or required to sell or surrender it all at once he himself would become a commodity (slavery).

Hence, in certain historical conditions, which they cannot claim to have always existed, just as they cannot claim to always exist in the future, conditions which we call peculiar to the capitalist epoch, we have the production of surplus-value, and the accumulation of it into capital. This is realized through the buying and selling of labor power, that is, through the organization of the wage earner by those who possess the money and the technical tools of labor.

Surplus-value and capital as economic phenomena appear later than exchange and exchange value, and also later than money.


11. Purchase of “labor power”

How then is payment determined for the commodity labor power (wage labor)? As with any other commodity, those who seek it pay the minimum possible i.e. they run elsewhere if they are offered better terms; so that the price tends to reach a minimum, given by the labor time required to produce that commodity.

Labor power is also a commodity in this sense, since in order to produce it the worker must provide for the expenditure of his own body, that is, he must procure:
     1. personal means of subsistence, such as food and a minimum of satisfaction of other needs;
     2. the means of subsistence for his family (without which the working class would become extinct);
     3. vocational education, which also involves time and expense.

This minimum is reducible to a sum of commodities which, demanded from producers, and in any case from possessors, must be paid at a price determined by the labor time required to produce them (just by our fundamental assumption). This price will be demanded by the worker to alienate his labor power (under average conditions, that is, disregarding interference from exceptional phenomena).

Having thus occurred the buying and selling of labor power, the capitalist, becoming its master, employs it. (We neglect here the other benefit of employing labor before actually paying for it, thanks to the custom of paying wages at deferred periods.)

The use of labor power, purchased at the right price, is done by applying it to raw materials equally purchased at the right price.

In order to understand how the right selling price of the finite commodities left at the capitalist’s disposal exceeds the sum of the fair prices paid (the birth of surplus-value), it is necessary to move from the field of circulation, where everything proceeds in the name of pure equivalence and full freedom, to the study of that of production, where instead the basis of in‑equivalence or surplus-value and class division are discovered.





 

 



[Prometeo, no. 6, March–April 1947]
[Programme Communiste, n. 3, 1958]


Part III - SURPLUS-VALUE
 (2)

12. Peculiarity of labor in the capitalist epoch

Every working process, independently of the type of social organization, consists of three elements: man’s personal activity, or labor power; object of labor, or raw material (found in nature but always with the addition of previous labor); means of labor, or instruments of production.

As long as we are in the presence of self‑employed workers (artisans) they own their own labor power, raw material, work tools. Consequently, the result of the working process, or product, belongs to them.

In the capitalist system the worker owns only his labor power; but he sells it so that the capitalist becomes the owner. To him belong also the raw materials and the instruments of work: by right the products belong to him.

The transformation of money into capital, the formation of surplus-value appear together with the separation of the worker from the instrument of labor and the product of his labor.


13. The birth of surplus-value

Let’s consider the productive process from the capitalist’s point of view. He goes to the market and comes back having bought – at their right price and value – as much the raw material as the work tools as the labor power.

He applies the labor power of his laborers, by means of his tools, to the raw material, and receives from them a certain volume of products. He returns to the market and sells them.

Let us consider the quantitative examination of such a value movement of value.

Let’s denote by V the value of the labor power (wages paid), by A the value of that part of the productive tools worn out in the group of operations we consider, by B the value of the raw materials employed; finally by F the value of the products obtained.

It is clear that F contains in full the values of A and B, i.e., production tools and raw material bought at the market. According to our basic hypothesis these values depend on the labor time required to produce these tools and materials.

As for the value of labor power V it is, as we have seen, related to the labor time required for the workers’ means of subsistence.

Every commodity, like materials and instruments, possesses an exchange value insofar as it possesses in its turn a use value, but in such a way that the two values are not comparable, nor communicable with each other (e.g.: I can reduce the value of a kilo of sugar to three hours of work, but I cannot refer its use value as food to a working time, but only to chemical, organoleptic qualities, etc. of the sugar). On the contrary, for the special commodity of labor power, if the exchange value, or market price, derives, as always, from labor time (necessary to produce the means of subsistence, as has just been said), the use value also lends itself to be measured precisely in labor time, because the use of this commodity is precisely labor: use by the purchasing capitalist of the labor of the selling wage‑earner.

Since the value of F (product) must then consist of the work time necessary to completely put together the products considered, it is clear that we will have:

Labor time for = Labor time for + Labor time for A + Actual labor time supplied by wage earners.

An equality between working times translates into an equality between the respective exchange values.

For the commodity labor power we must consider no longer its exchange value (wages), but its use value, reducing this to the time of work.

If, to fix the ideas, each hour of labor corresponds to the value of £3, the working time of the raw materials, since they are worth B pounds, will be B:3; of the instruments of production A:3; of the product F:3. If the worker has worked 10 hours, the equality between the working times before written becomes:
F
 £3 
= B
 £3 
+ A
 £3 
+ 10 (expressed in hours)

Back to values:

F = B + A + 10·£3 (expressed in pounds)

This is what the capitalist gets from the sale of the product. The figure B and the figure A he has spent in full because they signify exchange value, i.e. market prices.

But the figure 10·£3 does not represent the exchange value but the use value of labor power (10 hours of work actually done, for £3, the general ratio for measuring values in labor time).

What do those 10 hours of labor power cost the capitalist? We have indicated their cost with V, which is their exchange value, their price (wage). Now, since this value depends on the means of subsistence and on the time absorbed by them, it is independent of the 10 hours inferred from consumption, and not from the production, of labor power. If another team of workers were employed to provide food, clothes, etc. for the capitalist’s workers who work 10 hours, it’s clear that for each of them and for each day less labor time would be sufficient: let’s say 6 hours. Apart from the new surplus-value which would accrue to the aforesaid workers if they were in their turn wage‑earners, or supposing these to be self‑employed, the price V will be determined by those 6 hours multiplied by £3.

That the time of 6 hours turned out to be less than the time of 10 hours is not an assumption on our part, but a fact which can be deduced not only from special calculations, however laborious they may be, but from the very fact of the existence of capitalism and its profits, which we are only endeavoring to discover, starting from our hypothesis about labor.

If the expenditure V per labor is 6·£3, the total expenditure results:

B + A + 6·£3

The proceeds from the sale of the product were:

F = B+A+10·£3 = (B+A+6·£3) + (4·£3)

We have for the capitalist a profit of 4·£3 = £12 which represents the surplus-value in the productive operation under consideration.


14. Summary of the demonstration

The question we have been asking from the beginning is to represent the phenomena of the present economy with quantitative laws.

Experience gives us facts:
   a) we have a mercantile economy, that is, the products of labor become commodities susceptible to exchange, and the exchange is made by means of the general equivalent called money;
   b) whoever owns money can use it to buy the instruments of production and obtain a benefit, a surplus-value from production by means of wage earners (we also have a capitalist economy).

Accepting the fact that the measure of exchange value is expressed by the quantity of money given for a commodity, that is, by its price on the market, when we place ourselves in average, normal and general conditions, we have stated the hypothesis that this value is proportional to the working time necessary to reproduce that commodity, always in average, normal and general conditions.

Having analytically examined the phenomena of exchange, from barter to the introduction of the general equivalent commodity, to the function of money – having eliminated all objections relating to special exchanges and to exceptional circumstances and all those deviations from the average which may occur to a greater or lesser extent – we have shown that in the circulatory field nothing but exchanges between equivalents take place.

However, in order to explain the fact that the owner of money becomes the owner of capital and realizes a profit which has as its starting and ending points exchanges in the market, we have discovered and stated that this is due to the acquisition of a special commodity, labor power, which, while requiring a given labor time for its production, makes available a greater labor time in its consumption.

This commodity is paid in fact, and in accordance with our hypothesis, at a price (wage) proportional to its production (subsistence) labor time. But it transmits to the product a greater working time, and therefore a greater exchange value, whence the surplus-value.

The meaning of all this in the social field is the following: as long as the worker (artisan) is able not to separate himself from the instrument of work and the product of work, and sells this for his total benefit, he recovers in the exchange value of this his entire working time.

But when capitalism appears – because of the accumulation of money on the one hand (the origins of which we will not now discuss: slavery, land feudalism, etc.) and on the other hand because of the discovery of technical means, which diminish the working time necessary to a given product through the use of machines, and because of the concentration of many workers – the price of the artisan’s product falls: in fact its exchange value is adjusted to the minimum working time technically necessary. It matters little on the market that the craftsman with outdated processes has taken longer.

Let us suppose that prices fall so low as not to compensate for the artisan’s slightest need, e.g., the artisan having to yield at the price of 3 hours’ labor the product of 12 hours’ work, while his means of subsistence are worth 6 hours. The artisan will have only to sell his labor power, for its exchange value of 6 hours, working 12 hours for the capitalist who, quadrupling the output of his work, is able to pay 6 hours for the labor power which on the market could only be exchanged into the value of 3 hours.

We have thus satisfactorily explained the fundamental phenomenon of capitalist economy (fundamental also in relation to those which preceded it) by formulating an important consequence of the theory of value (first enunciated by Ricardo): the doctrine of surplus-value (Marx’s central discovery) is already contained in the following theses: on the market, only equivalents are exchanged; all the profit of capital arises from the purchase and employment of labor power.

The quantitative laws of this doctrine remain to be formulated (3).



[Prometeo, no. 7, May–June 1947]
[Programme Communiste, n. 10, 1960]

15. Constant capital and variable capital

As we have seen, the money anticipated by the capitalist to acquire the means of production and raw materials appears entirely in the price of the product. This is why we call this fraction of capital, constant capital.

Raw materials and instruments are of two kinds: some reappear in the product, others disappear as they are used, such as fuels and are called auxiliary; instruments of labor, such as machines, installations, buildings, are taken into consideration only for the fraction of their value actually spent during the productive operation considered.

The money advanced instead for the wages of the workers, that is for the purchase of labor power, reappears in the sale of the products increased by a surplus-value, and we shall call this variable capital.

We had summarized the balance of the capitalist operation in the two formulas:
 – expenses:
   B + A + V (raw materials + tool wear + wages)
 – revenue:
   B + A + V + S = F (raw materials + tool wear + wages + surplus-value = value of the product)

We then have: B + A = constant capital, which we denote by C, and V = variable capital.

Calling K the total capital advanced, S the surplus-value, and K′ the capital gained at the end we have:

K = C + V

K′ = C + V + S = K + S


16. Rate of surplus-value

Rather than knowing case by case the absolute quantity of surplus-value realized by the capitalist, it is more interesting to know the relation in which surplus-value stands to the capital which produced it.

It is very important to point out that the capital which is actually susceptible to produce surplus-value is that advanced for the purchase of labor power, that is, variable capital V. As for constant capital C, it reappears integrally in the product and in itself does not give rise to any increase.

It is for this reason that, wishing to define a quantity whose measure gives us the idea of the intensity of production of surplus-value, Marx assumes as the rate of surplus-value not the ratio of this to the whole of capital, but the ratio to variable capital alone.

So, denoted by s the rate of surplus-value:
s  =   S 
 V 

In the quantitative example we have given V was 6h⋅£3 = £18. The surplus-value was 10h⋅£3 - 6h⋅£3 = 4·£.3 = £12. The rate of surplus-value is s = £12 / £18 = 66.66%.

Passing now to examine working time, and referring for the purpose of fixing the ideas to a single day of a single workman and to the number of hours of which it is composed, which we shall call t (in the example 10 hours), a new quantity is defined: the work required and the relative time required. By such we mean the time or number of hours that the worker would have to work in order to transmit to the product a value exactly equal to that which he was paid for his labor power. In our case the workman was paid at the rate of £18, i.e. 6 hours’ labor. If he worked 6 hours he would reproduce exactly the value paid to him as wages, that is the value equivalent to his subsistence: in this case surplus-value would disappear, and with it the reason for the existence of the capitalist enterprise.

However, the worker works 10 hours instead of 6, and we distinguish the 10 hours into 6 hours of necessary work and 4 which we will call surplus-labor, calling this time surplus-labor time.

Let us repeat: necessary labor‑time is that which would suffice to reproduce the value of wages; surplus‑time or surplus-labor that the worker works in further, and which produces the difference in value, or surplus-value, for the benefit of the capitalist.

As the values are proportional to the working times in which they are produced we have:

Surplus-labor time   Surplus-value

 = 
Necessary labor time   Variable capital (wage)

These two ratios reduce to the one we have already indicated as the rate of surplus-value; hence the theorem: the surplus-labor divided by the necessary labor gives the rate of surplus-value.

In our example the written proportion would be:

4h / 6h = £12 / £18 = rate of surplus-value = 66.66%.


17. General law of surplus-value

It is also possible to show this by other means.

Let us summarize the notations; remembering that we refer to a single worker and a single day’s work:

V = Variable capital or daily wage
S = Surplus-value
s = Rate of surplus-value, i.e. S/V
t = Hours of work
n = Hours of necessary work
e = Hours of surplus-labor
z = Production of value per hour.

The worker transmits to the product the value (abstraction of constant capital) V + S, working t hours. So in one hour the worker produce the value:
z  =   V + 
t

Now we want to calculate the necessary work time n in which the worker produces the value V. By definition in n hours the worker produces the value

V = n·z
n = V/z

So, knowing the hourly value production, one division is enough:
n  =  V
 V
 + 

We have thus found n.

Very simple is the calculation of e (surplus-labor):
 
e  =  t - n  =  t -  t·V
V
+
 =  t·V + t·S - t·V
V
 + S
 =  S
V
 + S

 

The problem was to find the ration of e (surplus-labor) to n (necessary labor); dividing one by the other in the respective formulae, we have:
e / n  =  t·S
V
 + S
 /  t·V
V
 + S
 =  S / V  =  s

 

Thus the fundamental proportion remains proved, which we repeat here for the sake of clarity: surplus-labor stands to necessary labor as surplus-value stands to wage capital; this common relation is the rate of surplus-value.


18. Demonstration of the fundamental law

To show that ascribing surplus-value only to wages and not to all capital is not an arbitrary assumption, let us take the example of a firm in which there is only variation in the proportionality of constant capital to variable capital; the exchange value or price of products, the price of raw materials and work tools remains the same, independently, so too does the wages and the work day.

If the price of finished labor is to remain the same, representing it as labor time, we are not obligated to imagine a change in the technical processes of production: we can choose an example (convincing for that matter even to those who do not start from our theory of value) in which the firm also comes to incorporate an earlier stage of processing, producing directly what it previously purchased in the market.

Suppose that a steel mill which previously purchased pig iron to convert into steel would take iron ore, from which pig iron is made, to be processed directly (see in symbols in §20).

It is evident that the capitalist will spend less on raw materials, the cost of ore is far less than pig iron, and although there is a relative increase in the tools of labor, the share of constant capital will decrease in total.

Even vulgarly it is recognized that the capitalist will make a greater profit because he will accumulate the profit of two per‑existing firms. But he will also realize a greater profit for the same total capital up front since, albeit for each kilo of steel he will also have the burden of the new plant producing pig iron, such a burden he also paid before in the market price of pig iron, rather increased by the profit from producing pig iron.

In other words, the capital advanced for a labor operation is always included in the selling price of the relevant stock of product, so with the same financial potential the capitalist will be able to produce the same kilograms of steel if not more.

But on that figure his profit has increased; and this is because the capital invested in obtaining the kilogram of steel now contains less expenditure on raw materials and more expenditure on the purchase of labor power. So it is the amount of wage capital that, with equal treatment of workers, with equal market conditions, varies in proportion to the capitalist’s gain. Thus one must refer surplus-value to the mass of wage capital alone and not to the mass of all capital.

And this is also valid socially speaking, since in the various portions of constant capital other portions of surplus-value from previous workings are included, assuming they were carried out by the capitalist mechanism. The pig‑iron capital was, with the portion not represented by iron ore and wear of plants, already affected by surplus-value, collected by the pig‑iron seller; the iron ore capital for the mine capitalist was affected by surplus-value drawn from the miners’ surplus-labor; and analogously can be said of the mechanical steel plants, of the pig‑iron industry, in the mine, finally succeeding satisfactorily – outside of pleasantries about pearl fishers and the like – our explanation which, both qualitatively and quantitatively, discovers in every exchange value a labor time, and in every profit a surplus-labor.

Marx warns against falling into the gross mistake of confusing the rate of surplus-value with the rate of profit. Vulgar economics understands the rate of profit to be the ratio of the capitalist’s net earnings (the difference between income and expenses over a certain period, e.g., one year, provided that the “asset” value of all facilities remains unchanged and any liabilities offset) and the total value of the capital invested in the facilities increased by the amount of money required to meet purchases of raw materials, payment of wages, etc.

Vulgar economics also distinguishes within profit an interest to be paid for invested capital, and the remaining difference, or actual profit of the entrepreneur.

It is not now the case to push further the comparison between that computation and the calculations we followed. Suffice it to consider that the counting of time includes our having kept in mind an entire work cycle, e.g.: that by which the kilo of steel is arrived at. The more the extent of time increases of that productive act increases, the more the profit of the entrepreneur increases and in general the rate of profit as well.

On the other hand, the rate of surplus-value depends on the degree of exploitation of labor power and is always much higher; Marx’s easy examples show that profit rates, e.g., of 10‑15%, can correspond to a surplus-value rate of even 100%.

However, as an exercise in applying the above, one could institute the calculation on profit in a company that would be transformed in the manner indicated in the example of the steel mill, assuming concrete figures for prices and quantities of ore, pig iron, steel, for wages, hours of work, annual days of work, etc.


19. Breakdown of the value of the product into proportional parts of the quantities of the product of the working day

We gave at the beginning the example of the product of the value F, which consisted of the value of the raw materials and the wear of the instruments (B+A = C, constant capital) and the value generated in a 10‑hour workday. We used to equate the exchange value of £3 with one hour’s work.

Now let us suppose that the value C is £60. We will then have:

F = C + 10·£3 = £60 + £30 = £90.

Of the £30 of value added by the worker, 18 = 6·£3 represented the wage or variable capital V; 12 = 4·£3 representing the surplus-value.

Let us suppose now that the product, worth £90, weighs 1,800 kg.

As we have £90 = £60+£18+£12, we can put 1,800 kg = 1,200+360+240 kg. We then have represented in proportional parts of the product the elements that constitute its value. 1,200 kg = £60 represent the constant capital; 360 kg = £18 represent the variable capital; 240 kg = £12 represent the surplus-value. Adding these last two parts, we obtain 600 Kg = £30 = 10 hours of work, which represent the total value produced by labor (both the necessary labor and the surplus-labor). That is, they would represent the value added for 10 hours of work to the value of raw materials and worn‑out tools.

This subdivision is legitimate but completely conventional; it cannot provide an interpretation of the productive process, because, if it is true that the £60 exist prior to the application of work as raw materials and machines, as parts of the product, but neither a pound, nor a gram can be obtained without work. We have here a purely conventional notation. It is necessary to convince ourselves that our conclusion on the distribution of the £30 of value of labor in wages and surplus-value is quite different; this distribution is provided to us by a law which adapts exactly to the technical, economic, historical and social characters of the studied phenomenon.

In a similar exercise we will divide no longer the 1,800 kilograms, but the 10 hours taken to produce them, into parts proportional to the elements of value. For just as there subsists, other things being equal, proportionality between quantities of products and their values, there also subsists proportionality between product value (and quantity) and processing time. In one hour 180 kilograms of weight and £9 of value would come out of the worker’s hands, that is, one‑tenth of 1,800 kilograms and £90.

So to the following subdivision:

£90 = £60 + £18 + £12

corresponds this other:
10h = 6.66h + 2h + 1.33h (10h = 6h40min + 2h + 1h20min).
So 6h40 min represent the constant capital, 2h the variable capital, and 1h20 min the surplus-value.

This representation can be interpreted in a misleading way (see Marx’s “Senior’s last hour”, Capital, Vol. I) by saying that out of the 10 hours, the worker works for the capitalist for only 1h20min. With such an argument it was intended to show that the 8‑hour day would have ruined the capitalist. Such an argument for us could only be in favor of the 8‑hour day! But experience shows sufficiently that the 8‑hour day is perfectly compatible with the production of surplus-value.

In fact, such an argument is equivalent to assuming that the worker also produces the raw materials and instruments, whose value represents, on the contrary, pre‑existing labor time.

The exact distribution according to our theory is as follows:
   £90 = £60 + £18 + £12 = value of the product.
   30h = 20h + 6h + 4h = value expressed in labor time.
   20 hours represent the labor contained, as value, in the constant capital purchased by the capitalist.
   6 hours the necessary (paid) labor.
   4 hours the surplus-labor (unpaid).

Reducing the workday to 8 hours would remove only 2 of the 4 hours of surplus-labor, assuming that associated phenomena (increase in labor productivity) do not at the same time reduce the work time absorbed by the means of subsistence, i.e. the necessary work.


20. Appendix: Calculation for the company referred to in chapter 18.

[Programme Communiste, n. 10, 1960]

General treatment of the case of firm 2 that utilizes the products previously processed by firm 1, demonstrating the legitimacy of attributing surplus-value to wage capital alone.

Firm 2 incorporates firm 1 for previous processing of its raw materials. This firm 1 produces in one year exactly the quantity B2 needed by firm 2: B2 = F1.


  Firms Two
separate
firms
Unified
firm
1 2
Deprecia­tion rate A1 A2 A1+A2
Auxiliary materials H1 H2 H1+H2
Raw materials B1 B2 B1+B2 B1
Constant capital C1=
A1 +H1 +B1
C2=
A2 +H2 +B2
C1+C2=
A1+H1+B1+
A2+H2+B2
 C1+C2-B2=
A1+H1+B1+
A2+H2
Variable capital V1 V2 V1+V2
Total capital K1 K2 K1+K2 K1+K2-B2
Profit S1 S2 S1+S2
Revenue F1 F2 F1+F2 F2

 

For constant capital, we distinguish:
C1 = A1 + H1 + B1
C2 = A2 + H2 + B2
Ctot = A1 + H1 + B1 A2 + H2 = C1 + C2 ‑ B2

 

Thus it has been demonstrated that, in the transition from two separate firms to a single unified firm:
  - Variable capital V1+V2 remains the same
  - Profit S1+S2 remains the same
  - Rate of surplus-value thus remained the same
  - Constant and total capital decrease by B2
  - Rate of profit has thus increased
  - Sales decreases by F1

The same profit, or surplus-value, S1 + S2, cannot therefore be the result of constant capital, which has decreased. So we rightly take as the rate of surplus-value its ratio to variable capital, which alone brought it about. If we were to put it in relation to constant capital or total capital, we would face the absurdity of finding a different proportion between the two terms of the ratio solely by virtue of the change in management of the two firms (4).



[Prometeo, no. 8, November 1947]

21. Length of the working day

The length of the working day is variable. It has a minimum which, under the capitalist regime, will never reach the necessary working time, and it has a maximum which depends on the physical limits of the worker’s endurance. By placing fully on the terrain of capitalist economy, by considering labor power as a commodity and the wage as its fair price, the worker, like every other seller, has the right to be protected by law in determining the quantity of the commodity he sells, that is, the time he undertakes to work in the day.

If this were not the case, not only would the canon of juridical equality among those who enter the marketplace be violated, but if the worker’s body were to be weakened, the number of years for which he would have the strength to work would be diminished, thus depriving him of a large part of his only private property: his labor power. By physically crippling the working class this would, moreover, prove to be in the long run to the detriment of the capitalists themselves, although any given entrepreneur pays attention to nothing but the pursuit of the maximum of working time.

Hence a struggle for the legal limitation of the working day, amply described by Marx in chapters that need to be not so much summarized as updated for the present day.

Rather, it is interesting to see what theoretical conclusions such an exposition leads to. Far from concluding with the apologia of social law, Marx ironically reduces the pompous catalog of human rights to its measly result, for the worker, of knowing how long he has “freely” sold himself, and how much remaining time belongs to him.

But this result, if it prevents the physical annihilation of the working class, does not detract from the fact that, as we know, a large part (surplus-labor) of even legally sold time consists of unpaid time.

What the workers need (Ch. X Sec. 7) is not to affirm a limit to the working day, but «to put their heads together and, as a class, compel the passing of a law, an all‑powerful social barrier by which they can be prevented from selling themselves and their families into slavery and death by voluntary contract with capital». These words are not to be interpreted in the banal sense of the introduction of the normal working day or collective bargaining and even of the wage fixed by law, but in the sense of the historical abolition of the principle which makes labor a commodity, and of the possibility of freely selling even a single hour of work, that is to say: of the abolition of capitalism.


22. Surplus-labor and capitalism

We have said that the production of surplus-value appears under the capitalist regime in the precise sense in which surplus-value is the difference in a commodity value which appears after a series of exchanges on the market.

But even before labor power was treated as a commodity on the (free) market, the worker was forced in different ways to give away large parts of his time for free (surplus-labor). That was the case for the slave economy, agrarian economy, etc., etc. But Marx observes that when the form of a society is not mercantile, or is scarcely so, that is to say, when commodities are more interesting for their use value than for their exchange value, the social order does not give rise to an excessive hunger for surplus-labor. The owner of slaves has no interest in making them work beyond a certain limit, because he generally consumes rather than sells the slave’s products, and he would have to pay for a new slave if the first one died or became unable to work. The feudal landlord makes the peasant work for free on his land on corvée days; although this system seems inhuman, it produces a lower rate of surplus-labor than modern capitalism (Chap. VIII, 2).


23. Capital and surplus-value

Up to this point the analysis has proceeded by imagining that the capitalist always pays the same price for labor power (constant wages), and that this price exactly expresses its value.

Under these conditions, that is to say, while holding the necessary labor‑time constant, capital, in order to satisfy its need of obtaining the maximum surplus-value, since this is given by V·s, can only follow one of these paths:
    1. increase the rate of surplus-value, or surplus-labor, that is, the working day – but we have already seen that historically, it tends to decrease;
    2. increase variable capital, and this can be done by increasing the number of workers. In this sense, capital is always taking new steps forward by transforming artisans, smallholders, etc. into workers, taking advantage of population growth, urbanism, colonization. However, despite this tendency to increase the mass of variable capital, which is the only means of increasing the mass of surplus-value, we can see that capital is increasingly forced to largely take the form of constant capital in modern production.

However, further analysis will show that the contradiction with the law of dependence between variable capital and surplus-value is only apparent (5)

On the understanding that the formation of surplus-value is the characteristic of capitalism, another observation needs to be made about the initial conditions for the capitalistic phenomenon to emerge.

The new master must have sufficient financial means to employ a minimum number of workers, such as is necessary to guarantee him enough surplus-value to not only improve his personal standard of living, but also to set aside a margin of money to be further transformed into capital. These lower bounds are very variable according to social conditions; we have here an example of a purely quantitative distinction that gives rise to a qualitative difference (between the artisan or master craftsman and the capitalist).

However, the technological transformation of production processes is not an indispensable condition for the establishment of relations of the capitalist type. Capitalism came into being using traditional technology at first. The revolutions in the field of technology, machinery, and the use of mechanical forces followed later on. For us, these innovations are, on the one hand, brought about at an ever‑accelerating pace by the needs of capitalism, and on the other, they represent the conditions that make it technologically and economically possible to abolish it.

 

 

 

  



Part IV - CAPITALISM AND EMPOWERMENT OF LABOR

[Programme Communiste, n. 4, 1958]


24. Relative surplus‑value

In every science, for the purpose of analysing a phenomenon, since it generally presents several variable magnitudes, the various aspects are first simplified by changing only some of them, and considering the others constant. Thus, for example, the law of gravity assumes a simpler form when the acceleration of gravity, or the intensity of the earth’s attraction, is assumed constant. But taking a step further, which would be indispensable for accuracy if the object, instead of falling from a small height, were to start from, say, the lunar orbit, it must be observed that, as the distance between the object and the centre of the Earth decreases during the fall, the gravitational force and the acceleration increase. Since we know this law, the inverse of the square of distance, we can study the fall at variable acceleration similarly to constant acceleration, only the results will be more complicated.

In a perfectly analogous way, whereas we have hitherto studied the production of surplus-value under the simplifying hypothesis of the constancy of all values, i.e. of commodities, gold, and labour-power (which means that we imagined the average quantum of labour required to reproduce the individual commodities, gold, and the means of subsistence remain unchanged), we will now go further and suppose that the exchange-value of the means of subsistence needed by the worker, i.e. the value of labour-power and wages, can vary.

In the previous analysis, the quantity of capital, the number of workers, the length of the working day and the time of surplus-labour varied, while the necessary labour remained invariable. We saw that the rate of surplus-value could only rise by increasing the working day, and its mass either by increasing the surplus-value rate itself or the mass of wage capital, which was only possible by increasing the number of workers. The surplus-value produced under such assumptions was called absolute surplus-value by Marx.

We shall now assume that wages can vary, with the exchange value of the means of subsistence being varied, so is the necessary labour time. We shall call relative surplus-value that which originates no longer from the simple prolongation of the working day, but from the diminution of the wage and of the necessary working time.

The hypothesis of a forced reduction in wages is not yet made here, the value of labour-power remaining. This fact is not uncommon but is nevertheless an exception to the generality of our investigation. We speak of a decrease in wages the worker’s consumption being equal, due to the decreased cost (value) of what he consumes. This can only happen if labour productivity increases for those firms producing the means of subsistence. For relative surplus-value to arise, it is therefore necessary that the labour productivity not just in the production of any commodity, but of the commodities that enter into the means of subsistence be increased.

Although the value of the commodity produced in the capitalist enterprise, in order to be sold, is still treated by us as a constant, let us pose the objection: how can it be explained that the capitalist, who introduces an innovation increasing the productivity of labour, while keeping wages and all working time unchanged, makes a higher profit?

In that case, for a time the capitalist will be able to sell at the old, higher price (or at a little less because, being able to produce more and having to capture a larger market, he will have to eliminate other producers with a relative decrease in price). But this benefit will be transitory because very soon the competition will force his rivals to introduce the new production method and force him to adopt the lowered price.

In order for the socially necessary labour time to be shortened, the increase in productivity will have to invest those commodities that form part of the worker’s means of subsistence, there will then be a definitive increase in surplus-value. This is unless the working class manages to raise its standard of living, i.e. the mass of its consumption, another fluctuation of variables still extraneous to our examination.

In any case, our example of the capitalist who has transformed his technique, even in the transitional period, has only raised the use-value of his workers’ labour-power relative to the social average: they give him not simple but complex labour, hence greater value for each hour of work. This is how, without changing wages, the necessary working time decreases, which is that in which the worker would reproduce his wages if he could sell the products himself, and receive the benefit of the realised innovation (after deducting the constant capital). Therefore, even in that transitional period, the greater surplus-value derives from greater surplus-labour.


25. Collaboration (6)

The stages through which capitalism realises more and more relative surplus-value, increasing labour productivity beyond the limit that the independent artisan worker could reach, can be reduced to the following: collaboration between workers, manufacturing, machinery.

Taking the trades as they are under artisan production, with the same distribution and the same working skills and instrumentation and tools of the worker in each trade, an increase in productivity can nevertheless be realised by having a large number of workers working side by side during working time. This not only compensates for the individual deviations be they greater than or less than the average work potential, but actually allows the same operations to be performed in a smaller sum of time.

Thus we have simple collaboration, which accepts without yet modifying it the same technical division of labour achieved in the artisan regime. However, the fact of collaboration raises the average output of human labour. This is a social benefit, the first for which historical credit must be given to capitalism. However, it does not realise collaboration under this social impulse, but only for the purpose of intensifying the production of surplus-value.

On the other hand, one should not believe that the capitalist order is indispensable to society wishing to enjoy the benefits of collaboration. Examples of collaboration on a large scale include ancient regimes in which dynastic military leaders, dynastic or sacerdotes could dispose of large masses of labour forces (Assyrians, Egyptians, etc.). Similarly, it must be assumed that, if surplus-value cannot be produced without collaboration, the social achievement of collaboration can be preserved even beyond the stage of surplus-value production.


26. Manufacturing

When we turn to manufacturing we see a radical change: the production technique of craftsmen has not fundamentally changed, but the old division of labour is revolutionised in a greater productivity.

Manufacturing achieves this in two ways. 1) To produce objects on which workers of different trades have to work (example of the carriage that needs the blacksmith, the carpenter, the tailor, the painter, etc.) these workers are all brought together in the same workshop, where they will always exercise not all of their trade but only that particular activity that is needed for the object in question. In this first case, the workshop brings together several separate trades, while greatly restricting the scope of each one. Each workman thus acquires greater skill and productivity in the special function on which he concentrates. 2) In order to produce an object that previously required the work of only one trade, (e.g. the production of pins), the workshop breaks up the successive individual operations of that trade by entrusting them to workers who specialise in that one. Thus one trade is broken up into many others.

In either case, in parallel with the specialisation of the worker, the tool is specialised, which, having to serve a single operation, assumes the form that allows it to be carried out more quickly.

These two forms are called the heterogeneous form and the organic form of manufacturing.

Manufacturing decreases the labour time required not only for the aforementioned reasons, but because it creates a distinction, which the medieval artisan regime attempted to reject: that between specialised workers and labourers, who always mechanically perform the same gestures. For this second category, by eliminating or decreasing the expenses for the apprenticeship period, there is a decrease in the value of labour power and an increase in surplus-value.

Manufacturing represents a step forward in the division of labour. But this is a process that began long before manufacturing and which can be examined with regard to society as a whole.

The fundamental basis of a social division of labour, necessarily accompanied by the exchange of commodities, is the basic fact of the separation of town and country. This fact is already advanced in the feudal economy: while the peasants remain scattered in the territory, in which the feudal lord is arbiter, the artisans concentrate in the cities with a very different system of material, intellectual and political life.

While the division of labour of the craftsmen supposes a great dissemination of the means of production among many independent producer-merchants, the division of labour of the manufacturing type requires the concentration of many means of production in the hands of individual capitalists.

Would it be possible to reconcile the great advantage of the social division of labour with a general social organisation without capitalism? Not only is this possible as a programme for the future, but there are examples in the past of communities living on the basis of an organised division of labour between trades and the common ownership of land (ancient India, etc.). Hence Marx says that, while the social division of labour is found in the most diverse forms of society, manufacturing is a creation of capitalism, but its real benefits will outlive capitalism itself.

Ancient writers on economics extolled the social division of labour because it increased the output of human activity: they had quality and use-value in mind more than quantity and exchange-value.

With the manufacturing era, political economy appears as a special science. Its writers see matters from the capitalist angle, that is, they see the division of labour as a means to produce more, increase surplus-value and capital accumulation, what they call the elevation of national wealth.


27. Machinery

The manufacturing industry, built on the narrow basis of the old trades, soon became insufficient and the transition to the stage of machinery took place, which began with the establishment of mechanical factories where the first more complex tools and devices already adopted in individual factories.

The introduction of the machine – while in turn (like the other two first stages: collaboration and manufacturing) representing a decisive step forward for the performance of human, social labour – is determined by the capitalist tendency to lower the price of commodities and produce more relative surplus-value.

Machine in the economic sense does not mean what machine is in mechanics and physics, i.e. any device that changes the intensity, direction or point of application of the force acting upon it. The wedge, lever, etc. are physically machines but economically mere tools. Nor can a machine be defined as an apparatus moved not by man but by other agents: animal, water, steam, etc. Speaking of machines, we will distinguish between machine tools and driving machines. These transform, by means of mechanical agents, heat, chemical, electrical energy, etc. into a given movement which, when appropriately transmitted, causes the machine tool or operating machine to perform acts and movements previously entrusted to the hand of man, equipped with a relatively simple tool.

But even machine tools that have human power as their motive force economically deserve the name of machines because man performs a simple and continuous movement. Here, human intervention becomes purely accidental as it can be replaced by a mechanical motor, just as an electric motor can be applied to a sewing machine.

It is well understood that, depending on the case, the worker always intervenes, either to guide and rectify the motion of the machine tool or to start the motor, such as guiding the sewing fabric under the machine needle or operating the motor switch.

In the first machines the worker had to provide the physical energy to move them. They began to replace man with beast, and followed the ancient practice of drawing energy from watercourses and wind. But the real mechanical revolution came with the invention of the steam engine, capable of driving large numbers of machine tools simultaneously. This was followed by the industrial application of electricity, allowing water energy to be used remotely.

The question arises as to whether our theory of value, springing from labour, and of surplus-value, springing from surplus-labour, translates well the economic fact of the use of machines and whether it explains how it is a source of relative surplus-value.

The machine takes its place among the elements of constant capital. That is, it transmits to the product a part of its own value. This value is smaller the greater the durability and resistance to wear and tear of the machine; it is the greater the more it consumes fuel, lubricant, etc. (We shall compute the value of fuel and lubricants among those of the indirect raw materials, which as well as constant capital, end up incorporated in the product). So the machine would seem to add something to the value and price of the product.

The value of the machine depends for us on the average social labour involved in its production. The less expensive the machine, the less energy it consumes, the more productive it is, in the sense that it adds less of its share to the value of the product.

There is no doubt that the machine contains more labour and is much more expensive than the simple tools of the craftsman or even of manufacturing. Thus, in machinery, the means of labour would appear to contribute more value to the formation of the value of the product. On the other hand, however, it occurs that the machine replaces – for the same product – a large number of workers, thus decreasing the wage bill, so that overall there can be a decrease in the value produced. Thus, although, in relation to the same value of products, the production facilities of machinery import a greater expenditure than those of manufacturing, the performance of the machinery is such that the value of the products (sum of labour required) is diminished.


28. Replacement of machines for workers

[Programme Communiste, n. 10, 1960]

The question is whether the machine saves labour costs more than it increases the expense of maintaining it. This benefit can be had even if, as is always the case, the machine costs much more than the tool.

Picking up on familiar symbols, we recall the company’s profit:

S = F - (A + B + H + wgv)

i.e,

 - income: F-Value of the product,
 - minus expenses: annual depreciation of fixed assets A; plus raw materials B; plus auxiliary materials H; plus variable capital V = wgv (number w of workers per g annual working days per daily wage v).

Recall also that the rate of surplus-value is

s = S / V

In this company, a machine is introduced with the annual depreciation rate A’. This machine consumes auxiliary materials of value H’. It eliminates w’ workers. The capitalist spends more A’ + H’. He spends less, however, w’gv.

He will find it convenient to apply the machine as soon as

w’gv > A’ + H’

Even when there is an equilibrium between the two lots, and the capitalist is not yet driven to introduce the machine, there would be social benefit in using it. For, while the lot w’gv represents paid wages, i.e. the value of labour power, the lot A’ + H’ represents price paid, i.e. the value corresponding to all added labour (necessary labour, paid to workers, surplus-labour, enjoyed by capitalists producing machines, and inside auxiliary materials). Socially, substitution would be beneficial because far fewer labour days were invested in the machines and auxiliary materials than the w’g saved, for the same product.

Let us now see what happens to surplus-value. Assuming also that the capitalist introduces the machine in pure balance of expenditure, variable capital will have fallen from wgv to (w-w’)gv.

Even assuming that surplus-value remains constant, the rate of surplus-value will have risen

from   S
 wgv 
   to   S
 (w-w’)gv 

For example: if the workers have gone from 100 to 50, the rate of surplus-value will have doubled. Thus we have relative surplus-value, i.e. surplus-value increased (so far only in his rate) without extending the working day.

It may appear that this is of no interest to the capitalist, once he has only shifted part of his investment from variable capital to constant capital without (for now) increasing profit. But this is only appearance. We will try further to reduce to a few formulas the complete comparison between Marxist analysis and the capitalist accounting system, reserved by Marx for the Third Book. The sum of constant capital A’ + H’ which our capitalist – the mass of surplus-value S having remained unchanged – has substituted for an equal wage expenditure, is itself the product of labour, which was not performed before (i.e. before machines and coal were needed). On this sum of product another capital (other as owner, but in reality the same as previously invested in the wages of w’ workers) has realised another surplus-value, thus the total surplus-value has increased.

Let us now consider that there is a large benefit in substituting a part of the expenditure on wages in the expenditure on the machine, as corresponds in reality to the spread of machinery. The profit S, if the price of the products sold remained the same, would rise greatly, and the rate of surplus-value (profit divided by wage expenditure) would increase for two reasons, because of the increase in the dividend and the decrease in the divisor.

In reality, the effect of machinery, when it is sufficiently generalised, is to make goods produced at lower cost, i.e. with less labour. And in fact – having reached equilibrium and returned to the general conditions of our hypothesis of investigation, that on the market everything is paid for at the right value generated by labour time – the products of the firm under consideration will fall in price in proportion to the lesser total labour they contain. They will have to come down, not because that was the capitalist’s aim, but because competition will force him to do so.

He will not, however, regret the innovation, and here is why. The product used to include labour, which has now decreased by w’g working days. It’s true that the labour-days contained in A’ + H’ appear in it, but these are much less, a) because of the surplus-labour that appears in A’ + H’; b) because we have assumed A’ + H’ to be less than w’g.

Therefore the product will be paid for at a lower price. The lower production costs will lower the unit cost of production in the ratio

A+H+G+A’+H’+(w-w’)gv
A
 + H + G + wgv
= new cost of production
previous cost of production

  A B C D E
Constant Capital 100 120 120 108 108
Variable Capital 100 60 60 60 54
Cost 200 180 180 168 162
Surplus-Value 100 100 100 100 106
Additional Profit 0 20 0 0 0
Product 300 300 280 268 268
Rate of Surplus-Value % 100 166 166 166 196
Rate of Profit % 50 66 55 59 65
Production Cost per Unit 10 9 9 8.4 8.1
Consumer Price per Unit 15 15 14 13.8 13.8
 Surplus-value, 100, and Volume of production, 20, are assumed
constant, as well as the working day and the value of wages.
A - Firm before the adoption of the machine.
B - After the introduction of the machine:
   - Machine costs 20,
   - 4 out of 10 workers laid off, lower wage bill of 40,
   - Selling at market price there is an additional profit
      of 20,
   - Growth of surplus-value and profit.
C - Mechanisation extended to all companies in the sector:
   - The market price falls and the surplus-profit disappears,
   - The rate of profit falls.
D - Mechanisation extended to sectors producing constant
      capital:
   - Rate of profit rises again,
   - Cost and market price still decreases.
E - Mechanisation also extended to the consumer goods sector
      of workers:
   - Variable capital and necessary labour are reduced,
   - Surplus-value and its rate increase,
   - Profit and the rate of profit increase again.

It would thus seem that profit also in the second case falls back to the S-value.

But if we make the hypothesis of a general equilibrium succeeded by the diffusion of machinery, we have as a consequence that the same phenomena considered for the branch of business we are concerned with have taken place in all the others, with a consequent reduction also in the price not only of the new products A’ (machine) H’ (coal) but also of the old purchases for A and H, and also in the means of subsistence and therefore in wages v. As a result of this general equilibrium the fall in prices will take place without diminishing profit nor reversing the increase to it brought about by the introduction of the machines. The mass of surplus-value will therefore have increased despite the fall in the price of products, the rate of surplus-value will also have increased, and the production of relative surplus-value will have reached its peak.

All this without yet considering the historical social effects of machinery, in the general increase in the mass of consumption and in that of the number of workers absorbed by industry.

Secondary effects of the machine, all of which compete to increase surplus-value, are: a) the possibility of utilising the labour of women and children; b) the possibility of prolonging the working day by requiring less effort and less attention; c) the intensification of work, i.e. the increased yield of work with the same amount of effort on the part of the worker, which can also compensate for the forced reduction in the number of hours worked per day.



[Prometeo No. 9, April-May 1948]
 
29. Other characteristics of mechansims

One of the consequences of the introduction of the machines was the immediate dismissal of large numbers of workers, which caused real uprisings followed by the destruction of the machines to the fury of the people. A classic example is the Luddite movement at the beginning of the 19th century in England, which was suppressed by the government with extraordinary violence.

The appearance of capitalist manufacturing had not produced similar conflicts, because, if opposition came to the new workshops of the craft guilds, there was no conflict between wage earners and capitalists.

Quite different were the consequences of the introduction of machines, which gave rise to real tragedies of misery. The workers could not understand that these inconveniences did not stem from the technology of the machine, but from its social use.

Many bourgeois economists at the time of the introduction of the machine were concerned to justify and defend the mechanical system, in spite of all its drawbacks, but of course they attempted to do so without admitting that these drawbacks stemmed from the capitalist management of machinery. Among other things, they enunciated the so-called compensation theory according to which the reduction in labour costs (wages) achieved through the machine is a release of capital that can be used elsewhere by ‘giving work’ to other workers. This reasoning is reminiscent of the vulgar one according to which capitalists, by consuming a large part of the collective product of human labour, give workers more opportunities to work and thus earn a living. Almost as if they were proposing not to consume that extra product equally in a fairer distribution system, but to give up producing it.

Returning to the theory of compensation, it suffices to note that, as we have seen, even if the diminished wage bill is greater than the value of the machine purchased, the former represents a much greater number of working days, while in the value of the machine, and in that of the difference saved or in any case invested by the capitalist, only a fraction of the wage bill appears, the remainder being covered by investment in other constant capital and surplus-value.

But the economists in question place themselves, on the ground of the repercussions on the labour and subsistence market, from the point of view of their law of supply and demand. On this ground too, however, one could criticise them. By decreasing the wage bill and the purchase of subsistence by unemployed workers, there will be a surplus in the supply of subsistence and it will fall in price. But there will also be a surplus in the labour supply and wages will fall. And in the companies producing subsistences the lower demand will produce more redundancies.

The conundrum of the contradictions of machinery can only be solved by condemning its capitalist social application. Society should save a great deal of labour with the machines, the mass of food remaining the same, at worst. But more likely growing as well. The average result would be less effort and more food. But machinery, by generating relative surplus-value, separates the worker from his food and takes a larger share of it away for the benefit of non-workers.

In reality, even in the capitalist regime, the introduction of the machinery, and its abrupt repercussions, have been followed by phenomena that have allowed – subject always to the intensified levy of surplus-value – the demand for workers to be extended, however, with the rise of new industries previously unknown and correlated to the production of machinery or to other needs of the mechanical system (railways, motor navigation, motoring, gas and electric lighting and heating, photography and cinematography, telegraphy and radio telegraphy and telephony, air navigation, etc. etc.).

There is no need here to pursue an analysis of the revolution brought about by machinery in production. The relations between the various markets are disrupted, the countries where industry first developed can flood foreign markets with their cheap products, and the other countries must reduce themselves to producing raw materials and subsistence for the industrialised ones. The labour made available by machines gives great impetus to emigration and colonisation. At the time of Marx’s writing, the United States was in such a relationship with England, i.e. it absorbed population and the products of industry, returning agricultural products and raw materials. This relationship has completely changed today, and, if not quite reversed, it does, however, create in American industry a competitor capable of overwhelming European industry.

Nor is it the case here to deal with the theory of overproduction crises, and the closely related phenomena of industrial and colonial-military imperialism.

Big industry, in a word, from the moment of its appearance upsets the social division of labour from top to bottom.

Equally, we neglect to summarise here the well-known problems raised by the factory regime and which are the subject of the claims of professional organisations and so-called social legislation (discipline, hygienic treatment, protection against casualties, disability, unemployment, night work, women’s and children’s work, etc.).


30. Large-scale industry and agriculture

Finally, in Marx’s text there is a mention of the effects of big industry on agriculture, a subject he has dealt with elsewhere. Marx emphasises that the damage that the new methods do to the producer due to the capitalist application of the new technical resources is accentuated; but he adds the thesis that intensive exploitation also depletes the accumulated fertility in the earth. This process is avoided by the later discovery of chemical fertilisation, which allows soil losses to be artificially replenished, however Marx’s social argument retains its value in that it means that the application of machinery to the land is unlikely to be feasible by capitalism, if even it has been able to overcome the contradictions of its application to industry relatively. It is necessary for the realisation of the agrarian technical revolution that the application of machinery be done on a social basis and with central rather than private directives. This view is confirmed by the contrast between the forward march of industry and the still backward state of much of the world’s agriculture, and with it also agrees the programmatic orientation of the socialisation of industrial capital as a clearly anticipated stage in the industrialisation of agriculture.


31. Historical events in the production of surplus‑value. Evolution of economic science

Summarising the path we have taken, we have analysed the exchange of commodities, recognising in the commodity a product of human labour which, instead of being consumed by the one who has produced it, is offered by him in exchange for another product that he needs; whatever the mechanism or the intermediary, the rule of this exchange is that it takes place between objects that cost on average the same amount of labour time.

The complex of those who work and exchange presents more and more intricate relations and, at a certain moment, after the exchange has become generalised, the division of labour extended, the currency introduced, we seem to witness the failure of our rule as the exchange differences in value, i.e. surplus-value, emerge. There are some (among the holders of money) who come to the market and leave having ‘gained’, i.e. with a greater sum of goods than they had brought in.

Even before the mercantile epoch and even on other grounds than the market, there were (and are) those who realised such a benefit in products that were not theirs; but in that case they were directly delivered to them without material exchange and by virtue of social relations that clearly revealed the character of relations of force; whether they were marauding tribes, hieratic or feudal military chiefs, slave masters and the like.

But since surplus-value appears on the mercantile terrain and seems to be realised through peaceful and legitimate relations, we recognise the appearance of capitalism. Such surplus-value would not appear to be an appropriation of other people’s products, and thus of other people’s labour.

In every epoch, surplus-value has enabled certain individuals and even communities to prevent everything produced from being consumed, allowing the accumulation of material things necessary for the life of ever more advanced societies, which is commonly referred to as wealth.

In the ages of antiquity it was evident to the first attempts to theorise economic facts that all surplus-value arose from appropriated labour without expenditure (we say from surplus-labour) and the origin of wealth was recognised in labour.

Of course there are riches not produced by man but offered by nature. But only for populations that are still sparsely populated and have primitive needs can they be enjoyed without labour. When, however, the economy was based not on the labour of slaves or the defeated in war but on that of peasants, who, for the Christian feudal lord, were morally men like himself, the production of wealth as a gift from nature was theorised, wanting to disguise the power relationship whereby the landowner obliged the peasant, in addition to working for his own consumption, to provide surplus-labour and surplus-produce for the feudal lord.

This conception that it is only agrarian production that provides surplus-value survives in the school of physiocrats.

When, after the great geographical discoveries, the land economy is overlaid by the worldwide spread of trade, the mercantilist school arises to uphold the absurdity that neither nature nor labour, but simple exchange produces wealth; surplus-value arises in every exchange; the fundamental law is the negation of our: every exchange takes place between non-equivalents.

But capitalism appears and with it new economic doctrines and new explanations of surplus-value and the origin of wealth. The great activity of manufacturing and industrial factories leads to the truth that all wealth comes from labour. Ricardo makes this theory triumph and his school proclaims that surplus-value emerges from the productive force of labour (Classical Political Economy).

At this point, capitalist class theorists are no longer those of a revolutionary class but those of a conservative class. They cannot proceed any further in the scientific investigation of the truth. If the new mercantile and industrial society has definitively broken all feudal and theocratic brakes on the modern development of the sciences of nature, it is far from being appropriate for it to remove the brakes on the development of the sciences of society.

Ricardo and his ilk know that value comes from labour, but they dare not conclude that surplus-value comes from surplus-labour, because then capitalist profit would have its cause not in an immediate ownership of modern organised labour, but only in the superimposition upon it of a compulsion.

Hence, while the official economists contemporary with Marx will argue with all sorts of reasoning that surplus-value is a ‘natural’ and ‘necessary’ fact, inherent in productive labour, and therefore society will unfold without ever abolishing it, the many subsequent schools will, under the pretext of objectivity and true positive scientific sense, collect a mass of material, but refuse to draw simplifying syntheses from it. Profit will become a statement of cash, an arithmetical difference between the two lots, but its causes will be wisely found everywhere, in the exploitation of natural resources, in labour, in the vicissitudes of exchange, and so on. It will be argued that the economy is not susceptible to the enunciation of scientific laws, or even of causal hypotheses, with the famous argument that the imponderable fact of human action plays a role, and it will be reduced to a simple statistic. Similarly, the constructions of mechanics and chemistry can be challenged because, despite innumerable observations and experiments, no one has ever seen the pure realisation of the law of inertia (which would be in the practical absurdity of perpetual motion), or a piece of real matter whose component ratios mathematically translate without error those given by molecular theory.

The Marxist solution, on the other hand, is crystal-clear: value and wealth originate from labour; exchanges only take place between equivalents; surplus-value does not necessarily occur where there is productive labour and exchanges of products, and it is not a necessary character of a high social division of labour: it represents surplus-labour, i.e. unpaid labour, and for it to be produced the necessary condition is a social relation of force that separates the worker from the instrument of production and the product, and that forces him to alienate his labour-power as the only means of procuring subsistence.

The cause and measure of capitalist profit lies in the appropriation of surplus-labour. The thesis that there can be no productive labour except where surplus-value is produced is false.

Marx proceeds with a method that vulgar critics describe as a cold analysis of capitalism, alien to approval or condemnation, which concludes in predicting the further gradual evolution of capitalism itself. The very fact that Capital is not a programmatic manifesto or a memoir of claims leads them to believe that therein lies the toleration of long further vicissitudes of the capitalist regime and therein appear as satisfactory and desirable claims on the part of the working class the legislative measures of England and elsewhere. These are set out in chronicling the stages of bourgeois development and analysed with the aim of demonstrating that economic theory, the enunciation and demonstration of which forms the author’s object, is well applied. The gross or deliberate misunderstanding is based on the fact that the book proceeds by scientific method, and the scientific method – applied to it, and by the school to which it gave rise, to economics, sociology and history – consists in discarding all ideological preconceptions of a moral nature as worthless. It is a matter, in the work of investigation, of ascertaining the facts as they are, extracting laws from them and, on the basis of these, following and predicting their course.

There is no need to say now how and why this task does not in the least contradict the integrative task of active intervention, not of ideal forces and inspired and creative individualities, but of collectivities operating in a broad or restricted field according to the succession of situations  (7).

We say this because we have in Chapter 16 of Part V an example of how Marx’s work should be understood and read.

The fact of surplus-value is first investigated according to the methods of experimental science, on the basis of a hypothesis that explains and measures well the established facts. Then the thesis now recalled, which claims surplus-value to be inseparable from productive labour, is examined. We first compare it with past data. It is not true that once productive labour appeared, surplus-value appeared with it. As long as the producer remains in possession of his instrument of labour, is able to procure the raw materials, and remains the arbitrator of whether or not to alienate his products, or in any case alienate them for his exclusive benefit, he works as much as is sufficient to procure the things he needs, i.e. for only as long as he needs to work. In the beginnings of society, if the labour forces acquired are minimal, the needs are also minimal, and, especially where climate and soil fertility are favourable, the necessary labour time is low. Forceful intervention is needed to subject members of society to each other, to force some to work extra time for the benefit of others. While it is therefore true that a certain degree of labour productivity is needed for the fact of surplus-value to appear, it is not true that this has its immediate cause in labour, because historically we find examples of labour without surplus-value.

Having thus made the comparison with the data of history, which suffice to refute the pretended and metaphysical necessity of surplus-value and profit, the third point of the deduction is an obvious corollary: it will be possible for surplus-value to disappear and with it capitalism, preserving the productivity of labour with the formidable increases received through the various phases analysed.

It is therefore not a question of proposing mitigations or preconceiving minor changes in the economic order, but of the most radical position one can think of, that is, the suppression of capitalism itself, getting rid of the pretended demonstrations of the necessity and social immanence of the hinges on which it rests. Elsewhere the next point is dealt with, namely that such a transition is not only possible but necessary, and elsewhere still, when dealing with problems no longer of science alone but of action, it will be shown how and with what forces positive action will be exercised in this sense, the necessity of which in no way contradicts the established historical determination.








Part V - ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE SURPLUS‑VALUE


32. Distribution of the value produced by labour between the capitalist and the wage earner

[Programme Communiste, n. 10, 1960]

Now that we have briefly followed the historical variation of the length of the working day, and of the technical productivity of labour, let us consider quantitatively the laws of these variations. In all that follows, let us consider constant the value of money, which is taken as the measure of value of every other commodity: that is, let us assume that the procurement of a kilo of gold always costs the same average labour time, and that the kilo of gold always represents the same number of monetary units. Resuming the previous example, the equivalence of one hour’s work with £3 thus remains fixed.

To the quantities previously considered let us add a new one, the productivity of labour, i.e. its capacity to produce in the unit of time more or less products. Let us call this quantity m, intending to refer with it to the average social productivity of labour. On the other hand, we call the intensity of labour its productivity in an individual firm, insofar as it can be higher or lower than the average general productivity. Thus, while the average productivity of an hour’s work may be equivalent to x grams of iron, y grams of cotton, 2 grams of gold, 3 pounds, if, on the other hand, a worker in a given firm is able, by his skill or superior means of production, to produce 2x grams of iron, 2y grams of cotton, etc., i.e. 2 hours of average work, we shall say that the intensity is double that average.

Setting aside completely the constant capital whose value passes unaltered in the product, let us consider the part of the value of the products due to labour, composed as usual of variable capital, or wage expenditure or compensation of the worker (V), and of surplus-value, or appropriation of the capitalist (S). We have called the surplus-value ratio the ratio s = S:V.

We always call t the number of hours of work. Let us now call L the quantity of the product, no longer annual but daily, and f its unit price, no longer total but for the part representing labour and surplus-labour (not the total price, including constant capital).

We shall then have

V + S = f·L = t·£3


1°) (Case 3 of ch. XVI) - The duration of labour varies

Instead of t hours t’ hours of labour.

Given t’ = αt, the quantity of products L will become αL and their value fαL = αt·£3. That is, the sum of wages and surplus-value has varied. What will have been the variation of each? In general the wage will remain constant, and all the increase will fall on surplus-value (assuming the variation is an increase). However, within certain limits, if workers give more hours of activity they will consume more subsistence, and it will be necessary to increase wages if we do not want to see the intensity and productivity of labour, which for the moment we assume constant, decrease.

Thus an increase in the day corresponds to an increase in the value produced, a certain increase in wages and a corresponding increase in surplus-value.


2°) (Case 2 of ch. XVI) - Labour intensity varies but the day is constant

In a given firm, without prolonging the working hours, we obtain more products in the same time, so that the intensity of labour, previously corresponding to average productivity m, becomes αm. Again, we will obtain more products, L’ = αL. Since there is no reason for their price to change on the market, we will collect more, i.e.:

fαL = αt·£3 = α·(V + S) = V’ + S’

This increase in V’ + S’ must be distributed over wages and surplus-value. There will be a certain increase in wages because the worker, working the same time but more intensively, consumes more and can always offer himself to other masters by substituting an other worker who produces less. If, however, the increased intensity depended entirely on a secret labour of the capitalist, he could also leave the wage unchanged (V’ = V) and carry over the whole difference to surplus-value.


3°) (Case 1 of ch. XVI) - The working day remains constant and, ignoring particular variations in intensity, the average productivity of labour varies in all sectors of production

As always, the quantity of products from L becomes L’ = αL while still being the result of t average labour hours. But, since this variation by hypothesis affects all commodities, including raw materials, instruments of production and subsistence, all prices will fall, and with them that of labour power. The price f becomes f’ = f/α, the wage bill V’ = V/α.

Then the proceeds from the sale of the product L’ will be

f’·L’ = f/α · αL = f·L.

Thus the labour day produces more product, but the same value:

S’ + V’ = f’·L’ = f·L = S + V

The sum of surplus-value and wages remains unchanged. But we have seen that the wage has decreased from V to V’, with V’ = V/α. Consequently, surplus-value has increased:

S’ = S + V - V’ = S + V - (V/α) = S + V·(1-1/α)

How will the rate of surplus-value have varied? It will have increased more strongly since S’ is greater than S, and V’ less than V. Thus the value of labour power decreases, surplus-value increases, and the rate of surplus-value increases.

The rate becomes:

s’ = S’ / V’ = [+ V(1-1:α)] / (V/α) = α·(S/V) + (α-1) = α·s + (α-1)

Since α is more than 1, we have that the rate of surplus-value has varied more than proportionally to productivity because, in addition to corresponding to the old rate s multiplied by α, the additional positive quantity (α - 1) must be added. Ricardo’s mistake was, although he saw the increase in the surplus-value rate, to believe it to be proportional to the increase in productivity and the reduction in wages.

To give a clarifying numerical example, given the wage V of £18, the surplus-value of £12, and the total product of £30 (6 hours, 4 hours, 10 hours), let productivity increase by 100%. We will always get £30 because, while the product will be doubled, say 20 kilos instead of 10, the price will be £1.50 instead of £3 per kilogram. The wage will fall in parallel from £18 to £9, the surplus-value will rise from £12 to £21, i.e. it will grow less than 100%. The rate of surplus-value was previously 12/18 = 66%, it now becomes 21/9 = 233%. The rate has increased by 350%, corresponding to a 100% increase in productivity.

The three cases examined can change with simultaneous changes in all magnitudes (4th case).

When, as in the first case, general prices do not change, the wage, or price of labour power, only changes as a consequence of greater surplus-labour (for a greater consumption of labour power). If, on the other hand, prices change due to changes in general productivity, it is the change in wages that directly causes the inverse change in surplus-value. Capitalism means that the increased productive power does not result in decreased average labour, but in an increased proportion between the withdrawal of a privileged class and the compensation of labour. This in addition to the other enormous social ‘liabilities’ caused by the maintenance of such a state of affairs.








[Prometeo, No. 10, June-July 1948]
[Programme Communiste, n. 5, 1958]

Part VI - THE WAGE


33. General law of surplus‑value

In this subject let us only recall that the exact expression designating, in our theory, the wage, i.e. the sum of money paid by the capitalist to the worker for a day’s work, is: price of labour-power, i.e. value of labour-power.

Classical economics strives to find the value of labour analogous to the value of any other commodity. In doing so, it falls into the misunderstanding of defining the value of the working day as the value transmitted to the products by the worker’s daily activity. Now we know that this value, corresponding to the consumption of the commodity ‘labour power’, is much higher than the value of it (id est: purchase value, market value, hence price of that labour power).

In vain, an attempt was made to resolve the contradiction by evading the observation that there is a share of unpaid labour, by referring to the possible fluctuations in the price of wages analogous to the fluctuations in any other price due to supply and demand. This law causes fluctuations or deviations more or less than an average quantity, which is the exchange value. Assuming that the abundance of a commodity in relation to needs obliges the incautious or unfortunate producers to sell it at a reduced price, this phenomenon, accompanied by the reduction of production, or the inverse phenomenon, are phenomena that lead back to equilibrium, and it is precisely the equilibrium figure of the price that we call value and that we seek to explain.

Thus for the commodity labour power and for wages. Irrespective of the play of supply and demand (as independent of further phenomena to be studied further on, such as workers’ and employers’ union resistance) in a regime of equilibrium, the wage is always strongly below the quantity of value supplied by labour.

In vain, therefore, classical economics tries to make people believe that in every purchase on the market there can be a benefit (surplus-price), and so occasionally in the purchase of labour power, surplus-value remaining a miraculous product of capital.

On the basis of these general guidelines, one can study the various forms of wages (hourly wages or piecework wages), the fluctuations in wages from country to country and from epoch to epoch (chapters XVII-XX).


GENERAL LAW

To conclude the first study of the procedure of capitalist production carried out in the preceding notes, we shall once again recall the expression of the fundamental law discovered by Marx

Rate of Surplus-value   =   s   =   S
V
  =   Surplus-value
Variable Capital
  =  
 
  =   Surplus-value
Value of Labor Power
  =   Surplus-labor
Necessary Labor
  =   Surplus-labor Time
Necessary Labor Time

«Capital is not only power to dispose of labour; it is essentially power to dispose of unpaid labour. All surplus-value – in whatever particular form of profit, interest, rent, etc. is subsequently crystallised – is by essence materialisation of unpaid labour time».

«The mystery of capital’s self-valorisation is resolved in its power to dispose of a given amount of other people’s unpaid labour».







Part VII – THE ACCUMULATION OF CAPITAL

34. Reproduction of capital

The capitalist process takes place in three stages: the first occurs on the market, with the conversion of money into means of production and labor power; the second is production itself; the third, which also takes place on the market, is the transformation of the products obtained into money. The combination of these stages, which are repeated indefinitely, is called the circulation of capital (as we have already discussed in relation to the circulation of commodities and the circulation of money).

Through this process, the original capital plus surplus value returns to the capitalist. This can have various destinations. First of all, in certain cases, the capitalist entrepreneur must share it with other capitalists, with the landowner, etc. Secondly, surplus value can either be consumed by the capitalist or re-employed as capital.

For now, we will simply discuss the accumulation of capital, i.e., its initial formation, its preservation, and its growth through part of the surplus value. We call the initial formation of capital primitive accumulation; its preservation in a constant quantity, simple reproduction; and its continuous increase through the addition of part of the surplus value, progressive reproduction.


35. Simple reproduction

Let us assume that the capitalist uses all the surplus value provided to him in each act of circulation as a fund for his personal consumption and that of his family, and that he always repurchases the means of production and labor power in the same quantity. We then say that he lives on the rent of his capital (although the word rent sometimes refers to the total surplus value, even if not all of it is consumed by the capitalist).

It is usually said that the capitalist has advanced the expenses of production, including the wages that enable the workers to live and maintain their labor power. But wage expenditure, or variable capital, is only a particular historical aspect of the so-called labor maintenance fund, which in every economic system ensures the perpetuation of production. Although this is a social necessity, it took forms that were not yet capitalist, as in the case of the small farmer or craftsman, who worked every day to produce only what is needed for his maintenance. Capital, having separated the workers from the means of production, appropriates all their products and not only does it not advance them, but it returns to them, at the end of the cycle, only a part of the products themselves, converting the rest into surplus value. When we consider the circulation of capital in the case of simple reproduction, and when it has reached a constant regime, any advance investment that can be claimed by moral or legal theories as justification for surplus value disappears.

Of course, if, instead of the established regime, we consider the initial period, an advance of value must be noted. This advance of value must represent labor without surplus value; it is therefore asserted that it is the labor of the capitalists themselves in other times. This explanation can be accepted, except for discussion when talking about primitive accumulation.

Let us assume that capital of £100 now yields a surplus value of £20 in each cycle. Assuming that the £100 represents the work of the capitalist and his right to consume the same amount, it follows from not talking about surplus value arising from unpaid labor of others that the capitalist could, by repeating five production cycles, turn the surplus value of £20 into rent five times over. He would then have consumed his original £100 of labor value. But after this consumption, not only does the £100 of capital still exist, which he could consume at his whim, but moreover, it is capable of producing indefinitely more surplus value. Therefore, even if we assume that the £100 was actually advanced once as labor provided or consumption saved by the capitalist, this does not explain how this advance is withdrawn not just once, but twice, three times, four times, a thousand times, and in theory an infinite number of times. Therefore, the advance, insofar as it implies a return, cannot explain the fact of surplus value or rent.

In other words, simple reproduction, however little the capitalist wants to consume, is enough to transform any advanced capital into accumulated capital sooner or later. Therefore, all capital is capitalized surplus value, just as all surplus value is unpaid labor. The initial labor of the members of the capitalist class, if we admit it, is covered by the first few years of rent (surplus value destined for consumption).

Thus, the capitalist mechanism, the creator of surplus value, did not arise simply because some people managed to work and not consume. Something else was needed for the production of surplus value to begin: the forced separation of the worker from the means of production and from the products, which forced him to become a wage earner. The supposed transformation of the artisan, bound by a thousand medieval regulations, into a worker free to negotiate the sale of his labor power, actually means a condition of domination of the capitalist class over the working class, an expression to which we give a material meaning insofar as it produces a material subtraction of labor and production like every other historical form of appropriation of surplus labor.

In simple reproduction, capital reproduces itself but, above all—leaving the worker only enough for bare subsistence and excluding him, except in very exceptional cases, from the possibility of accumulation, anticipating in turn labor and value—it reproduces, that is, preserves and defends the social relations of force proper to the capitalist regime (and this by the mere fact of simple reproduction, and by mere compliance with state laws that guarantee exchange between private owners, leaving everyone theoretically equal rights).


36. Progressive reproduction

If, instead of spending surplus value, it is used again in addition to capital, there is an increase in capital, which will yield greater surplus value. If, for example, £250,000 has been advanced in a production cycle, of which £200,000 is constant capital and £50,000 is wages, and if the rate of surplus value is 100%, £50,000 of surplus value will be obtained, and capital will rise to £300,000. By investing it in another cycle, the constant capital will be £240,000, the variable capital £60,000, and the new surplus value will be of the same amount. The next time, the capital could be £360,000, and so on.

In general, therefore, when examining the overall picture of production, we must ask ourselves how the surplus value realized in money will be converted into capital, since additional labor power, raw materials, and tools processed in other productive acts must therefore be found on the market. As for the first requirement, we have already seen how the capitalist mechanism ensures the production and numerical increase of workers. As for the products that can be converted into capital (i.e., not intended for consumption by capitalists or for the subsistence of workers), they must appear as a surplus in total production.

For clarity, let us consider the period of one year: total production must thus be composed of: a part that reconstitutes the constant capital (C) intact; a part that represents subsistence exchanged for the sum of wages or variable capital (V); finally, surplus value (S) or net product. Of this, one part goes to the personal consumption of capitalists, another part, which must be capable of being transformed into capital, must be realized materially in additional subsistence, in raw materials to be processed, in tools and machinery.

Thus, if £250,000 were the entire world capital, £200,000 of products would reform the constant capital; £50,000 would be subsistence (wages). If £10,000 of the £50,000 surplus value were consumed by the capitalists, £40,000 would go to new capital, provided that of the total annual product, worth £300,000, there were materially £32,000 of additional means of production and £8,000 of subsistence.

If we ask where the capitalist got the original £250,000, we answer that it came from his work or that of his ancestors. Assuming this for a moment, things do not change, however, for the additional capital of £40,000. This is nothing but surplus value, i.e., unpaid labor. The same labor power and means of production in which the £40,000 is invested in the next cycle are taken from the net product, that is, from what remains after the return to capital of all its advances, and therefore from surplus value and from the labor taken without compensation from the working class.

We have come to the conclusion that the more unpaid labor capital has taken, the more it will take. This seems to contradict the fundamental law of exchange between equivalents, which would require the opposite formula: the more you take, the more you have to give back. Needless to say, the solution to the contradiction lies in the discovery of surplus value, whereby the special commodity labor, exchanged at its value, gives those who use it a higher value.

This explains why the same right of property has regulated the commodity economy since every producer has his product at his disposal and brings it to the market, and why it continues to regulate it even after the rise of capitalism, which has separated the producer from his products.

It would be a mistake to believe that commodity production could evolve in a non-capitalist direction and that the appropriation of surplus value could cease while the commodity regime of exchange and distribution (free trade) remained intact. This is because only when labor power becomes a commodity does commodity production become dominant in the economy and all wealth circulates on the market. The right to private property becomes identified with that of capitalist appropriation, not only as the right to private ownership of the means of production, but also as the right to ownership of consumer goods. The phrase in the text, «the great illusion is that of certain socialist schools which imagine that they can break the regime of capital by applying to it the eternal laws of mercantile production», would require lengthy commentary if, instead of expounding the theory and critique of capitalist economics, social programs were being expounded and discussed. Socialism is not only an economy in which the means of production pass from private to collective ownership, but above all one in which all products are collective and collectively distributed; all circulation involving the exchange of wages between private individuals is abolished and replaced by a central distribution mechanism which, in parallel with the mechanism that distributes work among producers, brings all products to the immediate consumer, unless it even makes them available without restriction (free transport, telephone, postal services, electricity, and so on for all other consumption).

Implicit in the above sentence is the condemnation of all corporatist, syndicalist, libertarian schools, and those advocating autonomous associations of professional or local producers (corporations, unions, communes, cooperatives), as well as those who admit a centralized socialism in production but allow mercantile distribution to continue.

* * *

The portion of income that capital consumes is used to purchase goods, which are obviously objects of consumption and not means of production. The bourgeois economy calls those who produce such goods unproductive workers, and those who produce goods purchased as capital productive workers.

It has insisted on recommending that capitalists consume little and accumulate much: of course, for capitalist production, accumulation does not mean hoarding money and commodities, but investing value in capital, i.e., in means of production. Classical economics has always maintained that it is characteristic of accumulation that the net product (surplus value) is consumed by productive rather than unproductive workers.

However, Smith and Ricardo’s thesis that all net product destined for accumulation is consumed by productive workers is erroneous. This would mean that all surplus value is anticipated as wage expenditure; we have seen that, on the contrary, part of it must be anticipated as constant capital and part as wage capital. It is true that the part of net product invested in raw materials also corresponds to products of other processes, which contain another part of wage capital; but then they also contain another part of surplus value, consumed by other capitalists.

We cannot therefore accept the capitalists’ thesis that «every part of net product destined for capital is consumed by workers». Nor is it yet necessary to attempt to reproduce the general picture of the circulation of wealth, which is an extremely complex and difficult problem.

We call the ratio between the parts of surplus value accumulated as capital and that destined for the consumption of the capitalist the magnitude of accumulation.

On the other hand, the accumulation of part of the surplus value is a necessity from which the capitalist cannot escape because it is a necessity of capital itself, personified in him, and of competition from rival companies. Therefore, the first capitalists vigorously preached abstinence from excessive personal consumption, which would withdraw capital from accumulation.

However, as a result of accumulation itself and the increased volume of surplus value, capitalists allowed themselves to consume more and more.

The concept of abstinence was elevated to a theory, claiming that all capital was value that the capitalist had abstained from consuming, and any accumulation was the product of capitalist abstinence. To answer this objection, which would demonstrate the necessity of the capitalist if one wants to achieve an increase in social wealth, it is first shown historically that pre-capitalist societies had simple and even expanded reproduction without capitalist surplus value and capital accumulation, as in India, where peasants were small independent owners paying an annual tribute to local lords. Even in an economy of this kind, part of the product is devoted to new and greater production, without the capitalist refraining from consuming it.

This reasoning is completed (even when this is not explicit in the text) with the conclusion: it is quite possible to allocate part of the social product (to fix the idea, let us say 20%) to additional means of production, without any need to attribute a much larger quantity (let us say 40%) to the capitalist, so that he may take credit for refraining from consuming the primitive part, while freely consuming the difference.


37. Variations in the magnitude of accumulation

Assuming that a constant proportion of surplus value is consumed and the rest capitalized (e.g., 20% and 80%, respectively), the amount of capital accumulated will depend on the amount, or mass, of surplus value. The same causes that influence the quantity of surplus value therefore influence the quantity of accumulation. These causes have already been examined. All other things being equal, they are:

a) Degree of exploitation of labor power, or rate of surplus value, or ratio of surplus labor to necessary labor. In this regard, we note that if the capitalist succeeds in prolonging surplus labor (by reducing wages or extending the working day), he will not be obliged, in order to increase the labor force employed, to increase the constant capital (or, more precisely, the fraction of constant capital constituted by machinery), as would be the case if, without being able to modify surplus labor, he hired new workers under the same conditions as the old ones. Therefore, all the increase in capital will generate an increase in net product, surplus value, and accumulation.

If the exploitation of labor began in the extractive and mining industries, which do not need raw materials, the intensified exploitation of the workforce would give greater impetus to accumulation. In agriculture, the effect is almost the same, apart from the need to invest capital in fertilizers, which are now supplied by the extractive or chemical industries. Finally, in manufacturing and factories, the increase in labor expenditure does not presuppose, when it derives from increased surplus labor, an increase in constant capital for plant, but only for the purchase of raw materials, and if these come from the increased net product margin of the extractive industries and agriculture, we will have as a final result a powerful impulse to accumulation.

b) Labor productivity – As we have shown, an increase in labor productivity leads to an increase in surplus value, even if the working day remains unchanged. Furthermore, although the total value of the product does not change, its material quantity varies, so that the same amount of money corresponds to more use value and the satisfaction of greater needs. Therefore, on the one hand, we have that as surplus value grows, accumulation grows; on the other hand, a lower income can satisfy the same needs of the capitalist; therefore, the latter can increase the percentage of capitalization. The new capital accumulated nominally retains the same value, but represents a greater mass of products, whether raw materials, tools, or subsistence goods intended to compensate the worker. Hence, this capital has greater accumulative power.

Calling the capital derived from surplus value ‘additional capital’, we find that, due to scientific and technical progress, the part of it invested in means of production (plant, machinery) takes the form of more efficient types than those corresponding to the old capital. The latter therefore remains depreciated. However, it must be renewed periodically, and this anticipation is already provided for in all our deductions and calculations.

This phenomenon is even less noticeable in the case of raw materials, whose consumption and renewal is annual if they come from agriculture, and on average much faster if they come from industry. Chemistry, by constantly discovering new useful materials, some of which were waste or worthless, transforms them into additional elements for accumulation. Therefore, to the extent that the power of labor favors an accelerated accumulation, it preserves and revives the primitive capital value. This property, inherent in socially divided human labor and the achievements of science, is falsely presented as an attribute of capital in order to justify the incessant appropriation of surplus labor (8).

c) Relationship between the consumption of fixed capital and its importance – It is clear that the capital invested in fixed assets (factories, roads, bridges, railways, machinery, ships, land improvements, canals, electrical installations, etc.) increases continuously, while the portion of capital consumed, say, in a year tends to decrease. This enormous value, maintained with relatively little effort, is equivalent to a free service provided by the labor of past generations. While the meaning of this process should suggest a tendency towards the satisfaction of all needs with a minimum of social labor, this contribution is attributed by official economics not to past labor but to current capital, so that surplus value (profit or interest) appears as compensation not for labor abstention but for the labor of other times. It is clear, however, that all these processes of increasing collective wealth are not the merit of the capitalist system but, on the contrary, starting from a given historical epoch in which we are living, are seriously hampered by it.

d) Magnitude of advanced capital – Another cause that influences accumulation, at a constant rate of surplus value, is the amount of advanced capital, which determines the corresponding surplus value and accumulation.

All these causes of accumulation do not therefore act uniformly but with increasing and accelerating rhythm (similar to the growth of compound interest). The line that can be drawn to diagram the intensity of capitalism is not a straight line but a curve that bends ever upward until it tends toward the vertical. This gives an idea of the fact that capitalism cannot last indefinitely but is racing toward its end at an accelerating pace.


38. Theory of the alleged wage fund

Some bourgeois economists claimed that, although the total mass of capital varies continuously, the fraction of it that is invested in the subsistence of workers remains constant, there being an almost natural limit (!), so that, despite their efforts, workers can only compete among themselves for this total. This theory does not deserve any criticism, as it is clearly refuted by the facts of the capitalist system.


[Prometeo, no. 11, November-December 1948]


39. General law of capitalist accumulation

We know that capital consists of a constant part (the value of the means of production) and a variable part (the sum of wages). We call the relationship between the means of production and the labor force the organic composition if it is relative to value; technical composition if it is relative to material quantities. Although the composition of capital varies greatly depending on the type of industry and also varies from company to company within the same industry, we can speak of the average composition of social capital by referring to the proportion between all variable capital and all constant capital (in a country or throughout the capitalist world).

Accumulation continuously increases capital, both in its constant and variable parts. Total expenditure on wages therefore increases, and this—by requiring a greater number of workers—gives rise to what is known as the demand for labor. Every year, a greater number of wage earners work than in the previous year. But the number of wage earners available, or the supply of labor, is not unlimited, and this generally leads to a rise in wages. Hence the general law: accumulation tends to raise the sum of wages.

This very important point requires some comments. First of all, since we have not yet dealt with the interplay of supply and demand with respect to any commodity, one might ask why we consider it with respect to labor power. Now, if it is true that the price of a commodity rises when it is scarce on the market as a result of competition between many buyers who need it, and vice versa, this phenomenon is equally likely to occur in one direction or the other and is very easily balanced by the elasticity of production and the modern efficiency of means of transport. The price diagram of a commodity shows fluctuations above and below a “compensation line” which we consider to represent value. The case of labor is quite different. First of all, its price-wage, while fluctuating around the value determined by the sum of subsistence costs, has the theoretical possibility of rising throughout the entire space of surplus labor, leaving the capitalist, who is the consumer and demander of this commodity, with a margin of profit represented by greater or lesser surplus value. Therefore, raising wages does not mean paying a pure loss premium because a necessary commodity is in short supply, but only suffering a relative decrease in profit in order not to lose all of it. Furthermore, it is not as easy to balance the excess or shortage of labor as it is to balance that of a material commodity, since it involves a greater or lesser number of people capable of working, which depends on circumstances that are partly beyond our control. Therefore, the possibility of wage fluctuations is of far greater economic importance than that of any list price.

Secondly, it should come as no surprise that the general development of capitalism is in the direction of accumulation and rising wages. This has been the case historically from the beginning of the fifteenth century until the time of Capital, and has continued to be the case since then, with ignorant critics claiming that this refutes the laws of the doctrine we are expounding. These critics confuse a downward movement of wages, which Marx never theorized, with the doctrine of increasing misery, which refers to the successive expropriation of artisans, small rentiers, small landowners, and small capitalists, as well as the fall of categories of unskilled workers into a sub-proletariat.

Therefore, the increase in the amount of wages was formally expected. But other polemicists and distorters have wanted to assert that this phenomenon means the evolution of capitalism in the sense of becoming more tolerable and civilized. This tendentious thesis also contradicts the text: «The more or less favorable circumstances in which the working class reproduces itself do not change the fundamental character of capitalist reproduction». This is explained by saying that simple reproduction leaves the social relationship between capital and wages and the terms of that relationship unchanged; accumulation increases both terms in the same proportions; it gives rise to more capital and a more powerful capitalist class, and it gives rise to a greater mass of wages and a more numerous proletariat, so that the relationship between the two terms remains the same, and their contrast remains the same. By accumulating, capital causes the proletariat to accumulate.

Having reestablished the correct interpretation, there is no need to continue analyzing whether the conditions of social struggle are influenced for better or worse by lower wages. If a very depressed regime becomes intolerable and prepares an upheaval, a greater sphere of needs for the working class at the moment when capitalism abruptly reveals its inability to satisfy it further can produce a deeper and more effective counterreaction.


40. Variation in the composition of capital: Concentration - Centralization

There is therefore an interplay between the demand for labor from the newly accumulated capital and the supply of labor limited by the number of people from whom workers can be drawn.

With its political triumph in the bourgeois revolution, capital tends to throw labor onto the market in order to pay it less. It therefore ‘frees’ the serfs and preaches population growth. The feudal and aristocratic classes that oppose this movement find representatives in the English landed oligarchy, the center of the struggle against the French Revolution, and their representative is Malthus, who, while ostensibly pitying the misery of the countless workers reduced to dividing the available wage capital into ever smaller portions, but attacking capitalism from a reactionary standpoint diametrically opposed to that of Marx, preached that while the means of subsistence grow in arithmetic progression, the population tends to grow in geometric proportion, leading to ever greater misery. The remedy he advocated was sexual abstinence to limit births. Needless to say, according to our school, population growth is offset by an increase in social productive power, but this must be freed from the domination of capitalism in order to rationally satisfy the needs of all.

Thus, there is a movement toward higher wages, but this “does not abolish the chains of wage labor”. Moreover, this general movement is not continuous and smooth. Even when wages continue to rise due to the accumulation of ever greater capital, despite the reduction in the rate of profit, this does not slow down the accumulation and increase of capitalist power. However, it may happen that the increase in wages is such as to discourage new capital investment and slow down accumulation. A balance is thus established as wages fall relatively and accumulation resumes its march. These fluctuations are analogous to the crises that capitalist production goes through. We should not believe that these periods of imbalance depend on population trends; it is not the variation in the supply of labor that causes wages to vary and influences accumulation, but rather the trend of accumulation which, together with the demand for labor, causes the rate of wages to vary and thus the ratio between paid and unpaid labor of the available working population. «The price of labor can never rise except within limits that leave the foundations of capitalism intact and ensure its reproduction in progressive quantities». Those who do not understand this do not understand the very principle and specific character of capitalist production (the text says this twice), namely, that there will be work for the worker only when there has been surplus value for the capitalist. This is enough to show how those who predicted a gradual increase in wages corresponding to a gradual decrease in profits and an evolutionary elimination of capitalism have remained faithful to the text we are dealing with.

In establishing that accumulation raises wages, we assumed that the composition of capital remained constant. In reality, this is not the case because, parallel to the growth of capital, accumulation brings about technical progress in labor productivity, which makes more complex and expensive tools and machines necessary. In other words, the proportion of constant capital tends to grow in relation to variable capital. Constant capital grows for two reasons: because, for the same amount of human labor, more valuable machines and equipment are used, and because, for the same amount of labor, more raw materials are processed as more product is produced.

However, the increase in constant capital relative to variable capital is not as rapid in terms of value as it is in technical terms. In fact, accumulation goes hand in hand with an increase in the means of production for the same amount of labor employed, but while the price of labor tends to rise with accumulation, the value of machinery and raw materials tends to fall as labor productivity increases. The phenomenon under consideration is not canceled out but slowed down. It should also be noted that, even if wage capital decreases relative to constant capital, it can increase in absolute terms if there has been a strong increase in the total mass of capital.

In conclusion, in order for the specific type of capitalist production to exist, there must initially be a certain accumulation of money convertible into capital in the hands of certain individuals (primitive accumulation, the genesis of which we shall see). But if accumulation generates capitalism, capitalism can only generate further accumulation, with the proportion of enterprises expanding ever more.

The primitive formation of capital is the concentration in the hands of one individual not simply of a sum of money, but through this sum control over the means of production and workers’ subsistence, which were previously scattered among many small independent producers. Therefore, the first accumulation is a concentration of capital. Further accumulation further advances the concentration of capital in a few hands, tending to make each individual capital larger. However, alongside this tendency of capital to grow, there is an opposite tendency towards the formation of new small capitals, both because the phenomena of initial accumulation are repeated and because large capitals are often divided, for example through inheritance.

At a certain point in the development of capitalism, the tendency toward concentration decisively prevails over the tendency toward dispersion.

We have the fundamental law of capital concentration no longer in the sense determined purely by accumulation, but in a more pronounced sense in that different centers of accumulation and concentration attract and unite with each other. This is how this phenomenon unfolds. Between capitalists, there is a war of competition with low prices. But low prices are normally achieved by increasing labor productivity, and this cannot be done, for a given degree of exploitation of the labor force, except by perfecting and renewing the means of production. This is possible provided that large amounts of new capital can be invested. Hence the success of the big capitalists and the ruin of the small ones, whose capital first tries to move to areas of production that have not yet been modernized, and then either disappears or passes into the hands of the winners.

In addition, with flourishing capitalism, credit can develop, a mechanism that allows those with large capital to make advances even greater than the total capital itself, while denying this facility to small entrepreneurs and keeping them under relentless pressure.

Competition and credit contribute to the centralization of capital, using this term to distinguish this second phenomenon from concentration, which is the immediate effect of accumulation.

Concentration can occur simultaneously for all enterprises, while centralization occurs to the benefit of some and to the detriment of others. Centralization has allowed giant capitalist enterprises to arise much earlier than simple concentration of individual capital could have done.

The establishment of joint-stock companies is a form of centralization, since what indicates the maturity of capitalism is the technical union of large masses of productive means and not the legal union of large values in the hands of a single private individual, a phenomenon also found in abundance in other economies (Cyrus, Crassus, India, etc.). The reference to joint-stock companies is in the text and shows how valid the trivial criticism is that the spread of joint-stock companies is a refutation of the theory of centralization.

Centralization, however achieved, accelerates the reproduction of capital in new investments and improvements in production. At the same time, the phenomenon mentioned above of the growth of constant capital relative to variable capital continues, so that if the demand for labor increases on the one hand because the total mass of capital increases, on the other hand it tends to decrease because the proportion of wage capital in the total decreases, not only because of new capital invested in more modern equipment, but also because of old capital, which soon catches up with these innovations.


41. Surplus labor population or “industrial reserve army”

Given the question of the increase in capital accompanied by a decrease in the ratio of the variable to the constant part, the question arises whether variable capital in absolute quantity, and with it the demand for labor, tends to increase or decrease. In general, changes in the composition of capital can lead to an increase, stagnation, or decrease in the wage fund.

The phenomenon can take different forms in different branches of industry, as there may be a compensation of labor demand between them.

We have already examined a question of this kind in connection with the introduction of machinery. In an enterprise, machinery is introduced and a certain number of workers are laid off, so that there is a decrease in the demand for labor. But the analysis does not stop there. Machines need labor to be manufactured, and machines process more raw materials, which creates demand for labor in other industries. It is true that machinery gradually conquers these industries as well, but the general increase in labor productivity allows for cheaper products and livelihoods, greater surplus value, and therefore new capital investments. In conclusion, the general trend is an increase in the number of wage earners as a result of the progress of accumulation, and ever wider strata of the population swell the industrial working class.

However, this development is by no means continuous. When the excessive desire to invest surplus value in new enterprises has pushed the number of workers to the maximum, products become superabundant. As soon as their distribution encounters difficulties, since they are no longer demanded by consumption, the so-called crises of overproduction occur. Large masses of goods remain unsold, capitalists stop or reduce the activity of their factories, and a large number of workers are laid off. To get out of the crisis, capitalism strives to produce at lower cost, making maximum use of all technical improvements. At the end of the crisis, a certain relationship is established between variable capital and total capital, which is lower than before. Production and accumulation resume, and with the increase in total capital, wage capital and the demand for labor also increase for a certain period of time. During this normal interval, the number of wage earners begin to rise again, and the supply and demand for labor are more or less in balance. But another crisis is not long in coming, so that the workers attracted in ever-increasing numbers are abruptly thrown back into unemployment. The succession of these alternating phases and the creation of this surplus of wage earners in relation to the needs of accumulated capital characterizes capitalist production.

Economists have interpreted this process in various ways, seeing its causes in population growth and formulating the famous population laws. However, the real population law of the capitalist era is only this: that the accumulation of capital, by producing a surplus of the working population or an industrial reserve army, creates a further condition for the existence and development of capitalism itself. This reserve is subsequently used in periods of growing production, then thrown out when the crisis breaks out. The succession of these crises occurred during the 19th century at intervals of about 10-11 years, with a tendency for the intervals to become shorter.

We will only mention that the first world war, while itself an effect of the race towards industrial overproduction, which sought to avoid crises by turning to foreign and colonial markets (“Imperialism as the latest phase of capitalism”), represented both the explosion of the crisis and the means of swallowing up a plethoric industrial activity. Its consequences were a succession of partial crises or even the events of a deeper general crisis (9).

It is a constant concern of capitalism and its theorists to form and maintain an industrial reserve army, favored by throwing artisans, peasants, women, children, blacks, Chinese, etc. into labor, or by campaigns for the intensive procreation of the native workers. Even the reactionary Malthus was concerned about the excessive reduction of births among the proletariat in an industrial country.

It is therefore not possible to make the movement of capital and the rate of wages dependent on the increase in the absolute numbers of the population, as bourgeois economists claim. They believed that the rate of wages depended on the supply of labor corresponding to the growth of successive generations, and that the decrease in wages, when capital could no longer employ all the laborers, decimated the proletariat through deprivation, reducing its fertility. On the contrary, demographic changes are phenomena with long-term repercussions compared to the frequent fluctuations in the rate of wages, which, as we have said, depend on the expansion and contraction of capital activity.

In conclusion, it is absurd to hope that the solution to the crises and contradictions of capitalism can arise from the providential law of supply and demand applied to wages. The phenomenon always works to the advantage of the capitalist class.

Naturally, bourgeois economists cried scandal and violation of the sacred law of supply and demand when workers, through economic organization, sought to mitigate the effects of mutual competition by bringing about joint action between those who have work and those who do not.

This is not the place to show that even trade union organization cannot prevent the general development of capitalism or overcome its principles. Its importance lies in attracting ever broader strata to the class movement, as is well known from other sources.



[Prometeo, no. 12, January-March 1949]


42. Forms of surplus labor

Marx’s Capital calls the form in which surplus workers, rejected due to technical improvements in factories and reabsorbed due to their increased potential and production, ‘fluctuating’. It calls the form in which technical improvements in rural districts make a large number of workers available, who are then forced to flock to the cities and offer themselves to industrial bosses (the phenomenon of urbanization), ‘latent’. It calls the form in which an excess of workers is created in both industry and agriculture, rejected by the improvements, and who offer themselves for highly exploitative jobs such as so-called home-based work (“sweating system”), ‘stagnant’. Finally, the last remnant of the surplus working population constitutes pauperism, not to be confused with vagrants, delinquents, beggars, and prostitutes, who constitute the non-working classes (underworld, thugs, etc.) and are particularly numerous in modern metropolises.

Regarding the pauperistic surplus labor force, it comprises three categories: workers who are able to work but unemployed, orphans and children of those assisted by public charity (these two categories are available to capitalism to return to active service in times of high demand), and finally workers who, due to age, disability, or obsolescence of their trade, are permanently unemployable.

Therefore, if it is true that with the progress of accumulation, the rate of wages tends in general to rise for workers who find employment, and if it is also true that the total wage capital and the number of workers tend to grow, then at the same time there is the creation of an ever-larger reserve army, composed of former artisans and small owners ruined or expropriated for transformation into wage workers, but exposed, along with their descendants, to the risks of unemployment and therefore of the blackest misery, despite the measures of charity, social legislation, and workers’ solidarity.

The more total capital and therefore national and social wealth (in reality, the wealth of the capitalist class) increases, the more industrial wealth increases and with it the domination of pauperism (see the enormous masses of unemployed in the capitalist countries after the war). All this constitutes the law of the growing misery of the proletariat, as opposed to the growing wealth of capital, which is not contradicted in the least by the increase – on a historical scale – in the wages of employed workers, nor by the improved standard of living of certain privileged categories, nor averted by social legislative measures within the framework of the capitalist system.

Bourgeois writers first urged workers to reduce their numbers if they did not want to exceed the needs of capital, knowing full well that the reduction would never be such as to cause them alarm. Later, they cynically admitted that this poverty in the lower classes was the best condition for the prosperity of the nation. Today, and after Marx, such statements are no longer to be found, hypocritical social philanthropy, demagogy, and the extolling of illusory remedies entrusted to associations and the state prevailing.

But the fundamental law of capitalist accumulation remains the same: all means of multiplying the collective forces of labor, which should contribute to raising the average standard of living, are applied to the detriment of the individual worker and become means of subjecting him to the domination of private capital. Whatever the level of wages, the progress of accumulation entails an increase in the relative surplus population; as capital accumulates, the condition of the working class worsens.







Part VII – ORIGINAL OR PRIMITIVE ACCUMULATION

[Programme Communiste, n. 7, 1959]


43. Historical forms of property and origins of capital

Money becomes capital, capital produces surplus value, this becomes additional capital, and thus capital is produced by the very mechanism of capitalism. However, for this to appear in history, the first capital had to be formed in a non-capitalist environment.

Classical economics, considering capital as accumulated value, i.e., the product of accumulated labor, asserts that the first capitals were formed by the labor and savings of their owners.

Now, if it is true that all value arises from human labor, it is not true, however, that the value produced by labor remains in the hands of those who have worked. In general, in the historical periods that have taken place so far, the fruit of labor has always been taken from the hands of the worker, and its accumulation by its direct creator has always been an exceptional case.

Contrary to the idyll that should reign in economics textbooks, in real history conquest, tyranny, robbery, that is, brute force reigns supreme.

The existence of state power and legal forms, even abstracting from obvious and hidden violations, has never meant a guarantee that the product would remain attributed to the producer. First of all, periods of social and political upheaval constitute abrupt transitions between one legislative regime and another, and civil or national wars always involve or entail vast expropriations, but even excluding these parentheses in the historical sense of the law, as we have excluded those in the personal sense (delinquency), we do not recognize at all in the various legal systems that have hitherto dominated the character of ensuring the producer the peaceful enjoyment of the whole fruit of his labor.

The law is guaranteed in its application by the material force of the state. We do not see in the state the impartial representative of collective interests, but rather the organ of the domination of one part of society, namely, of a class.

Consequently, the law is in each case the codification of the rules that serve to enforce the interests of that class. The state and the law therefore exist precisely when one class needs to exert continuous coercive pressure on others, and since economic interests lie at the basis of these relations, to carry out the systematic expropriation, to a greater or lesser extent, of the productive energies of the subjugated classes. The state and the law, therefore, mean precisely a system that serves to transfer the fruits of labor from workers to non-workers.

In order to understand the social structure and political events of a given era, we ask ourselves which classes are in conflict, which of them holds power, i.e., the state, and before that, we ask ourselves what relationships or forms of property the system in force establishes and preserves. In turn, property relations can be explained by analyzing the forces of production, i.e., the technical resources available to labor and its organization and distribution among men. The productive forces are, in every era, the material and physical resources used and the groups of men assigned to work. These productive forces are contained in a specific pattern of property relations, which are guarded by the law and state power. But for complex reasons, such as population growth, the transformation of production techniques as a result of new inventions, the opening up of communication channels, and so on, conditions arise in which the productive forces, and first among them the class that provides labor, come into conflict with the existing forms of property. Hence an era of social revolution, with the struggle between the class that benefited from the old system and a class that had hitherto been dominated, the breaking of the forms of property, i.e., the overthrow of the state, and the rise of a new state with a different law.

Returning to the question of primitive accumulation, it is through an analysis of this kind that the solution must be sought, and not in the naive and tendentious assertion that labor and abstinence created the original capital. However, it will be useful first to recapitulate the most elementary application of what we have said to the history of society.

At the beginning of work and economic and social life, there are few people, while the available land is vast. Peoples are divided into small wandering tribes that practice primitive agriculture and pastoralism, cultivating in common an area of land occupied under the direction of a chief who is at first the head of the family. Individual property and class divisions did not yet appear in this period of primitive communism.

The very mobility of the tribes led to their encounters, the expansion of productive resources and needs, conflicts, and the imprisonment of the vanquished. Military and priestly castes appeared; through a long process that we are far from discussing here, we moved into the era of slavery. A class of men is forced to work in the service of others, without the possibility of refusing or leaving, and can be owned and alienated as private property, since the division of land, livestock, and all other property among the members of the ruling class, or free men, has already taken place.

However, even in ancient societies, not all free men were landowners or slave owners; only a minority of them ended up with enough property to be able to live without working, while the rest owned little land, which they cultivated with their own hands and without slaves, or were small artisans who produced and sold manufactured goods. At this time, the law, and with it philosophical and moral ideology, justified the exploitation of slave labor, their sale, and even their killing. The class of large landowners (patriciate) mostly held the state, in struggle with the class of small farmers and artisans (Greek democracy, Roman plebs). The foundation of production remained agriculture, despite the spread of navigation and trade and the emergence of money owners and even the beginnings of capitalism.

With the new conditions that followed the fall of the Roman Empire, Christianity, and the abolition of slavery, the basis of production remained agrarian, and the land remained divided among large feudal landowners.

The former slaves were freed under the new Christian law and morality and could not be sold. However, they were transformed into serfs, i.e., agricultural workers who could not leave the land, while the feudal lord enjoyed most of the fruits of their labor. However, small free farmers also disappeared, reduced to serfs, and only a few groups of city artisans were able to achieve relative independence from the feudal nobility by organizing themselves into professional guilds in the so-called comune.

In this feudal society, the ruling class was the landed nobility, whose allies and instruments were the clergy, the army, and the absolute monarchical state (despite the conflicts that led from primitive feudal decentralization to the formation of large state units).

In these various social forms, not only do we not find the same law and the same moral ideology in force, but we cannot even establish certain legal and moral principles common to all that would constitute the so-called natural law. The very relationships between people are sometimes protected and sometimes condemned by both written law and moral sense. Therefore, we do not find in force the famous principle that the product of one’s labor belongs to the worker, a principle that should explain in an honest and peaceful manner the initial accumulation of capital.

Almost always, we find the worker in a position where he cannot dispose of the means of production he uses and of his product. He is separated from them by legal force, whether he is an ancient slave, a medieval serf, or a modern worker. We find the worker not separated from his tools and products only in primitive communism and in the handicrafts of various epochs, as in the small peasantry; this does not exclude that even these social classes must not surrender part of their product to others, suffering an extortion of surplus value in various forms of tribute, taxes, usury, and various rights.


44. Conditions for the formation of capitalism

The capitalist order directly succeeds feudal land-owning society. For this to function, there must be, on the one hand, the accumulation of money (and this condition has long been realized in the hands of landowners, merchants, usurers, financiers, slave traders, etc.) and, on the other hand, a mass of workers separated from the means of production and therefore forced to sell their labor power.

The key to primitive accumulation is therefore the historical movement that created this separation. The feudal order prevented this in two ways: through serfdom, which prohibited peasants and their children from leaving their feudal estates; and through the guild system, which used extremely complicated regulations and special magistrates to force artisans and their children to work in a specific trade and in small workshops with a limited number of apprentices. The laws of the feudal state sanctioned this situation and prevented the emergence of the capitalist economy, while also oppressing the nascent bourgeois class, made up of merchants and bankers in the cities or former peasants who had become artisans, emancipating themselves from serfdom and creating small factories for the production of manufactured goods in the ‘burgs’, as opposed to the lord’s castle.

This class formed a revolutionary ideology that condemned feudal constraints and restrictions in the name of a whole philosophical theory of freedom and legal equality, but this campaign for the liberation of the people was only the ideological equivalent of the economic necessity of making available to production a mass of ‘free’ sellers of labor.

On the other hand, production needs were pressing irresistibly for intensified world communications, increased trade, and a growing need for increasingly complex products of labor.

The capitalist entrepreneurs had to take the place not only of the corporate master craftsmen but also of the feudal owners of the sources of wealth; their advent appears as the result of a victorious struggle against the power of the lords and their exorbitant privileges, against the corporate regime and the obstacles it placed in the way of the free development of production and the free speculation of man over man. The knights of industry have supplanted the knights of the sword; they have won by means just as vile (the text means: by leading the nascent masses of the proletariat, unaware that the era of democracy and political representation meant the triumph of the regime of free exploitation of wage earners, into revolutionary struggle) as those used by the Roman freedman to become master of his own lord (Chapter XXVI). «The starting-point of the development that gave rise both to the wage-labourer and to the capitalist was the enslavement of the worker. The advance made consisted in a change in the form of this servitude, in the transformation of feudal exploitation into capitalist exploitation». Of course, there is also the substantial progress of having broken the bonds that opposed the introduction of collective labor and of having introduced a high technical division of labor.

Our criticism rejects all democratic apologetics for the bourgeois revolution, and this is a fundamental aspect of it; however, in rejecting the philosophical and legal presentation of this ideology, it does not deny the historical value and revolutionary character of the introduction of capitalism, which created the conditions for further developments. «Although we come across the first sporadic traces of capitalist production as early as the fourteenth or fifteenth centuries in certain towns of the Mediterranean, the capitalist era dates from the sixteenth century. Wherever it appears, the abolition of serfdom has long since been completed, and the most brilliant achievement of the Middle Ages, the existence of independent city-states, has already been on the wane for a considerable length of time». In this period, every political revolution reflected the advance of capitalism. Every act that expropriates masses of small producers, whether artisans or peasants, is a victory for capitalism.

The process takes two forms. In general, the abolition of serfdom allows the formation of widespread small rural property. But capitalism needs the former feudal serfs to become not independent producers but wage earners, and therefore supports any measure that deprives small farmers of their land.

In Italy, the process takes on special forms. At the end of the Middle Ages, northern Italy and part of central Italy were at the forefront of production technology (as well as science and culture). Not only banking and commercial capitalism but also manufacturing capitalism developed there earlier than elsewhere, especially in Florence, Genoa, Venice, Pisa, etc. Feudalism therefore disappeared earlier there, and serfs were attracted to the flourishing cities. Master craftsmen became true bourgeois (the wealthy populace), and the numerous apprentices were transformed into a true proletarian workforce, so much so that the struggle between the two classes made its appearance (the Ciompi revolt, etc.). Then the geographical discoveries of the late 15th century completely changed the currents of the universal market, capitalist manufacturing declined, the bourgeois class was weakened at birth, the feudal class lacked the energy to come together in a unified political creation, workers returned to the countryside where small-scale farming spread, and the country fell into a prolonged state of social and political stagnation.



[Prometeo, no. 13, August 1949]


45. The expropriation of the peasants

The example of England is quite different. There, serfdom disappeared in practice towards the end of the 14th century, and the vast majority of the population became small independent peasants, although their legal possession of the land was justified under feudal constraints. The feudal lords retained a great deal of land, but they managed it through independent tenants (in this case, one of the first types of capitalists, who employed the former serfs as wage laborers, some of whom were landless day laborers, while others were small landowners who had time left over from working their own land). However, the day laborers themselves were granted four acres of land with a small rustic house, and they also shared in the enjoyment of vast communal and sometimes state-owned property.

Meanwhile, cities prospered and manufacturing and industrial capitalism emerged; this was hungry for labor and soon obtained it. The political revolution made royal power a bourgeois instrument, and the new bourgeoisie allied itself with a new landed aristocracy (landlords) which, supported by capitalism, undertook the expropriation of small farmers, pouring labor into the cities. With the help of the law, the large landowners reclaimed their ancient fiefdoms, expelling the peasants and transforming them into sheep farms, which required little paid labor. Subsequently, the lords also usurped immense hunting grounds where cultivated land had previously been. All this resulted in the disappearance of small rural properties and the transformation of peasants into proletarians.

In the mountainous part of Scotland, common ownership of land was preserved for a long time (until the end of the 18th century). Here too, the lords, at first purely nominal heads, with the complicity of the bourgeois state, expropriated and drove out the unfortunate mountain dwellers. The despoiling of church property, the fraudulent alienation of state domains, the plundering of communal lands, the usurping and terroristic transformation of feudal and patriarchal property into modern private property, the war on huts—these are the idyllic processes of primitive accumulation. They conquered the land for capitalist agriculture, incorporated the soil into capital, and abandoned the docile arms of a fireless and homeless proletariat to the industry of the city (Chapter XXV).

Characteristic features of state intervention in favor of the rising bourgeoisie, in addition to measures to expropriate the peasants, were the ferocious legislation against beggars and vagrants who did not want to work, based on torture, flogging, branding with hot irons, and the like; and wage legislation that fixed a maximum wage and absolutely prohibited workers’ coalitions. This whole process took place in England even before the bourgeois political revolution; the first edicts date from 1350, the last wage laws lasted until 1813, the atrocious laws against trade unions were repealed in 1825, but some traces remained until 1859; the legal recognition of trade unions came on June 29, 1871. But it was only reluctantly and under the threatening pressure of the masses that the two great parties of the English parliament renounced the laws against coalitions, after the parliament itself had for five centuries acted as a trade union of capitalists against the workers (Chapter XXVIII).


46. The struggle for the “liberation” of the workers

In France, we find equally fierce laws against vagrants. Here, feudal rights disappeared more slowly, and widespread small rural property, which was more resistant than in England due to the very different technical characteristics of agriculture, took a long time to develop.

It is very interesting to note, however, that immediately after the revolutionary storm, which seemed to liberate, along with the bourgeoisie the proletarian fourth estate, its ally, workers’ associations were banned. A law of June 14, 1791, punished any agreement between workers aimed at improving their conditions of employment as “detrimental to liberty and the declaration of the rights of man”. The reason for this bourgeois opposition to workers’ associations is clear to us: it was to allow free competition to obtain labor at the lowest price. The speaker at the assembly is consistent in saying that associations of people of the same profession “tend to resurrect the guilds abolished by the revolution” because in both cases, despite the profound historical diversity of the phenomenon, they are constraints on the free recruitment of labor by capital. Within the framework of liberal theory, the prohibition of workers’ unions is no less appropriate: the representative state is the only body that encompasses and protects all citizens on an equal footing. Each individual enjoys freedom while remaining isolated except for his or her connection to the unitary state. Class privileges have legally disappeared; any association of members of the same social class tends to form a state within a state, a caste within general legal equality, and must be prohibited. In economics, liberalism wants the unlimited play of individual private interests; the state generally protects contracts between private individuals, but cannot tolerate collective actions and contracts.

The decree of 1791 was in fact respected by the Terror and the Girondins, by Bonaparte and by the Restoration. If, in a very late period, parliamentary democracy yielded to the recognition of trade unions, it did so in contradiction to its pure doctrine, as all state intervention in economic and social relations contradicts it. The contradiction with the principles confirms their futility, designed for the “ideological mobilization” of the masses, who are deluded into believing that they are free and sovereign. However, there is no contradiction with the interests and class politics of capital: in the first period, it has only reaction to fear and no restraints on securing the best economic conditions for accumulation, but in the subsequent period, the formation of a strong working class poses the problem for capitalism of not only economic but also political relations with the proletariat: although prohibiting coalitions may depress wages and increase surplus value and accumulation, the capitalist class calculates that this may sooner lead to a social struggle in which the very principle of surplus value and accumulation will succumb; it is therefore generally in its interest to allow trade unions and to prescribe by law certain sacrifices on the part of individual capitalists to make the wage system less intolerable.

But the great French democratic revolution was no less consistent when it deprived workers of the right to unionize than when it instituted compulsory military conscription, despite the common mistake today of considering advanced democracy to be the antithesis of anti-worker reaction and militarism!


47. Genesis of the agricultural capitalist

We have examined the conditions that allowed primitive accumulation with the formation of a wage-earning class. Let us now see how the first capitalists appeared. In England, the agricultural capitalist, i.e., the large landowner, appeared before the industrial capitalist. Let us therefore discuss the former.

An agricultural property can be managed in various ways by its legal owner. Under slavery, he makes slaves who are his property work on it; the land is also his property. The slaves are technically directed either by another slave or by a free slave who has been emancipated and is paid by the master. Under feudalism, the land is worked by serfs, but the master rarely concerns himself with organizing its management. Mostly, each peasant family has a small field, a fraction of the produce of which is given to the owner (tithe); in addition, the owner keeps for himself the best pieces of land, on which the peasants are obliged to work for a certain amount of time (corvée).

Once the serfs have been emancipated, various cases become possible. Direct administration, or self-sufficiency, was possible when the owner possessed not only the land but also capital stock (livestock, seeds, fertilizers, tools, and later machinery, etc.) as well as cash capital to advance wages to day laborers, who were directed by a foreman employed by the owner. This was the first form introduced by the English landlords, although the former serfs were not only day laborers but also small landowners and usufructuaries of small fields.

Soon, however, the foreman became a sharecropper. Metayage, or rather sharecropping, is a form of management in which the owner provides the land and part of the movable capital, the sharecropper provides the rest of the supplies, provides the labor by hiring wage earners, and finally the product is divided in proportions agreed between the owner and the sharecropper. Here we are talking about large sharecropping applied to vast single estates where the sharecropper does not work but hires day laborers, as distinct from small sharecropping where the land is divided up, even if it is a single large property, into many small farms worked personally by the sharecropper and his family.

The large English farmers soon became rich as the small independent farmers and day laborers, who had previously owned a little land themselves, became impoverished for the reasons already mentioned. Thus, the sharecropping system gave way to outright leasing. Rent is a form of management in which the owner contributes only the land and rural buildings; all movable capital belongs to the tenant, who hires the workers and keeps all the produce for himself. He pays the owner a rent in cash, so his income is divided into the landowner’s ground rent and the capitalist profit of the tenant-entrepreneur. It should be noted that both the rent and the profit of the enterprise arise equally from surplus labor, divided between the owner and the capitalist by virtue of a class alliance under the shadow of the state, since we deny that bare land and not labor can be a source of wealth.

We also distinguish here between large and small rents. The latter is not capitalistic in nature, as it involves small areas of land worked directly by small tenant farmers who own few and poor means of production, similar to artisans, but without land. We note that even advanced agricultural techniques correspond to the unified management of large estates. This is direct administration or large rent, depending on whether the legal personalities of the owner and the capitalist coincide or not. On this basis, large-scale labor, the division of labor, and the mechanical industrialization of agriculture can be achieved.

On the other hand, smallholdings are generally backward forms (except in the case of land that is exceptionally fertile for small-scale cultivation) and even when there is large land ownership, it is managed in several small plots rented out at low rents and by small sharecroppers. Incidentally, the second type of situation was that of large Russian estates after the emancipation of the serfs and the abolition of patriarchal communities. In these cases, small farms accompany large estates.

The transition to large farms is a task requiring long technical and economic progress. The legal separation of small farms from the exploitation of large estates can be an immediate event: in reality, the land is not shared but remains technically divided as before, while at least one form of extortion of surplus labor (what used to be land rent) is immediately abolished.

Returning to England: the first large tenants quickly became wealthy, partly because in the 16th century gold, silver, and therefore money decreased in value, all goods became more expensive, but wages rose much later. As the lease agreements were very long-term, the tenant saw his income from the sale of products increase, while his wage costs and rent actually decreased, so that he became rich at the expense of the wage earners and the owners.



[Prometeo, no. 14, February 1950]


48. Genesis of industrial production

The expropriation of small farmers and their replacement by large agricultural enterprises not only allowed the nascent capitalist industry to find masses of wage earners who did not come from the guild crafts, but also provided the process of primitive accumulation with its material and economic elements; in fact, since the reduced number of farmers did not decrease the production of agricultural commodities, as this was offset by the greater exploitation of day laborers, technical improvements, and the greater yield of large-scale labor, a large mass of subsistence goods became available, as well as a quantity of agricultural products that could be used as raw materials for industry (spinning and weaving of linen, cotton, wool, etc.). After expropriation, raw materials are purchased by the manufacturing capitalist, along with the available means of subsistence, in the form of wages paid to hired workers.

The transformation of agriculture, therefore, not only provided and supplied the new proletarian class and the new capitalist landowner, but also made available to the new urban capitalist his constant capital (raw materials to be processed) and his variable capital (subsistence). This did not happen only in England but also in many parts of Central Europe, as in Westphalia at the time of Frederick II, where the linen-spinning peasants were expropriated of their land, and if they wanted to have linen to work and subsistence to consume, they had to go to the large manufacturing factories as wage workers. In other words, the expropriation of the rural population, by determining the supply of raw materials and subsistence, creates a domestic market for capital.

But this destruction of all domestic agricultural industry is not complete at the time of manufacturing, since the latter always leaves certain initial operations to small craftsmen or small workers who are partly farmers scattered throughout the countryside. It is only the introduction of machinery that definitively eradicates this primitive and scattered production, absorbing all operations into the factory and conquering the entire internal market for manufactured goods for capital.


49. Genesis of the industrial capitalist

We now come to the central point: the appearance of the first industrial or factory capitalist (strictly speaking, the tenant farmer is also an industrial capitalist).

We will not deny that in some cases the small initial capital was formed from the accumulated labor of independent artisans and even of some wage workers; much more often, however, it was the head of a guild or master craftsman who became a capitalist, as he naturally had more legal and illegal means of setting money aside.

With workers now available to hire and raw materials to purchase, all that was needed for the capitalist to emerge was the possession of a sum of money for the initial advances. Now, since earlier times, there had been private individuals who had accumulated money in proportions far greater than those achievable through the fruits of labor; that is, there were two types of capital that did not yet have the character of industrial capital, namely usurious capital and commercial capital.

We have already said that the benefit realized by those who invest money in usury (meaning by this word any interest-bearing loan) and in commerce is always, in a more or less direct measure, coming from surplus labor and is therefore surplus value. However, the characteristic form of capitalist production is still lacking, namely the direct sale of labor power, production remaining in the hands of workers who are not separated from the means of production and the product. Since they do not have enough money to advance their small amount of raw materials and other things, nor do they wish to wait for the time and place most convenient for exchanging their product, they must cede part of their earnings to the money accumulator who performs these services for them; and by ceding their earnings, they cede part of their labor.

Usurers and merchants therefore had money at their disposal but could not transform it into industrial capital with the feudal constitution of the countryside and the corporate constitution of the cities. Old societies fight against the formation of capital with very strict laws on usury and with a moral campaign against those who live off usury and even merchandise; not only the warrior lord but also the adventurer, whose figure borders on that of the brigand, is considered more respectable than the merchant.

The severity with which usury was punished in the ethical framework of medieval consciousness is demonstrated, among other things, by the place it occupies in Dante’s system of punishment. Usury is part of violence (although the relationship between the lender and the payer of interest appears materially peaceful). Just as the blasphemer is considered violent against nature because he breaks the law of nature, so the usurer is called violent against art, that is, against human work, because he breaks the moral law according to which no one should be deprived of part of the fruit of his labor. We are not surprised that Dante’s morality does not see the same crime in the income of the feudal lord, nor does it show any indignation against the slavery of classical antiquity, although it repudiates it in the name of Christian principles. At that time in history, it seemed morally repugnant that money should yield money to those who do not work, a fact that is now affirmed as being in accordance with religion, nature, and sound sociology. And in the final verses of Canto 11 of Inferno, Virgil explains to Dante the unworthiness of the usurer, invoking Aristotle’s Physics, according to which human art must be the source of life (work is the source of value), and Genesis (you will earn your bread by the sweat of your brow), while the usurer takes another path and therefore offends nature in its follower, Art (work). It is curious that this does not offend the rich man who inherited his wealth and who is punished in the previous circle as violent towards himself and his possessions if he squandered them instead of passing them on to his heirs. The contradiction could be explained theoretically with some scholastic subtlety, but, as we have noted, it is immediately clarified by our critical method through historical and social circumstances. The inalienability of real estate is one of the cornerstones of the feudal system.

Once the barriers preventing usurious and commercial capital from hiring labor and becoming modern capital have fallen, resistance continues: artisans demand that merchants be prohibited from becoming manufacturers; new manufacturing centers are established in new locations rather than in the old cities governed by guilds, springing up in export ports and sometimes within a special territory established by the monarch.


50. The factors of original (or primitive) accumulation

Therefore, it is not labor but ancient mercantile and usurious accumulation that essentially explains primitive accumulation. However, what gave it a formidable impetus was the exploitation of newly discovered lands and communication routes, the discovery of precious metal deposits, the conquests and plundering of the East Indies, the slave trade, and the like... idyllic poems. As soon as the capitalist era began, great wars broke out for commercial and colonial domination, and hegemony passed from Portugal to Spain, Holland, France, and England (the threat of German or Russian hegemony was eliminated by the world war, but other formidable competitors arose to challenge England’s position: Japan and, above all, the United States; the Second World War brought the latter to the forefront).

We can see the methods of primitive accumulation already in full development in the hands of England at the time of its crusade against the French Revolution: among them are the colonial regime, state debt, the modern banking system, and protectionist customs. Some of these methods are based on the use of brute force, but all without exception make use of the power of the state, the concentrated and organized force of society (for the benefit of the ruling class) to violently precipitate the transition from the feudal economic order to the capitalist economic order and shorten the transition phases, as well as to counter the opposing nascent force of the proletarian class tending to overthrow the capitalist economic and state order. Indeed, force is destined to facilitate the path of all old societies that are on the verge of transformation; force is an economic agent.

The history of the atrocities committed by whites in the colonies and the means by which they enriched the famous East India companies and their high officials would be endless. It is well known that Catholics and Protestants denied the Native Americans a soul because they were not mentioned in the Bible. The Puritan and Protestant colonists of America put a price on the scalps of the Indians; everyone knows the methods of capture, transport, and use of black slaves; everyone remembers the opium wars and the premeditated poisoning of entire populations of ancient civilizations for the benefit of English capital.

The colonial regime greatly developed navigation and trade and produced merchant companies protected by governments, which favored the accumulation and concentration of capital. The conquest of the colonies ensured outlets for the products of nascent manufacturing, while the treasures extorted from the natives through forced labor and all other means flowed into Europe as capital. While today industrial supremacy implies commercial supremacy, since competition on foreign seas is free from political constraints, at that time the opposite was true, so that the most powerful colonial nation, Holland (17th century), was the one with the most capital and raced ahead on the road to accumulation.

Public credit, i.e., the system whereby the state borrows money from private individuals in return for interest, began in the Italian commercial cities of the Middle Ages. It is natural that such a system favors accumulation, since small and large private capital, whether usurious or commercial in nature, and exceptionally the savings of artisans, who would find no other way to produce surplus value, become industrial capital in the hands of the state, which has other means at its disposal to hire wage earners (maritime and port work, arsenals, shipbuilding, public works in general, etc.). Furthermore, public debt represents the capitalist imprint on the state: the king of France is still the envoy of God and has power over the life and death of every subject, but he must fear a few financiers and loan sharks in Paris, to whom the law denies the slightest privilege. It is natural that the first bourgeois economists should praise public debt for the impetus it gave to all forms of capitalism; it anticipated the creation of large enterprises that would otherwise have had to wait for a slow process of concentration, and it paved the way for joint-stock companies and the trade in negotiable securities which, although they represent, like government bonds, receipts for money lent, circulate themselves as money. For public credit was followed by private credit.

The banking system arose from state credit. The bank is an institution through which private individuals lend their capital. Many small sums of money find no enterprises in which to invest themselves, and are therefore deposited in a bank. The bank, having large sums at its disposal, lends them in turn to a few large entrepreneurs who have little capital but good opportunities of finding wage labor and markets for their products. These entrepreneurs pass on part of the surplus value to the banker, who in turn passes on a smaller part to the various depositors. The division of the surplus value extracted from the working class in varying proportions is explained by the greater or lesser risk run by the person who has advanced the money. According to the theory of risk, the state offers great security of repayment and therefore pays minimal interest, large semi-state banks pay higher interest, small banks pay even higher interest, and entrepreneurs, especially those with few valuable assets and engaged in new ventures, pay very high rates. Finally, the loan shark, who lacks decent and convenient means of getting his money back from his victims, demands fabulous rates. In reality, all these debts are fractions of the surplus value that has come out of the loan sharking exchange between labor and wages. However, the mechanism of banks and interest-bearing securities at fluctuating market prices allows the development of speculative struggle among capitalists to subdivide the available rent over the total social production.

In speculative struggles, the decisive weapon is not so much a lack of scruples, which is within the reach of every imbecile, as the availability of large masses of value. The whole phenomenon, in addition to spurring investment and initial accumulation, greatly favored the high concentration of capital.

With public debt and banks, international credit arose, allowing primitive accumulation in new countries with available workers but lacking subsistence, raw materials, and the money to purchase them elsewhere. Venice lent vast sums to Holland, which in its decline lent to England; in the 19th century, England lent to the United States. But the capital lent, reproducing itself progressively, was soon able to repay the initial advance and become autonomous. Since the end of the First World War, the United States has been the creditor of the whole world.

Public credit, being based on state revenues with which interest must be paid, gave rise to the modern tax system. This became another formidable element of primitive accumulation, both by ruining small farmers and artisans to the point of expropriation and by diverting large amounts of value from the consumption of the poor classes to the capitalists lending to the state.

Finally, we have the protectionist system, whereby an industry whose formation encounters difficulties is favored by the state in various ways, imposing heavy customs duties on similar products manufactured abroad and imported into the country, so as to raise their price domestically, allowing domestic manufacturers to make higher profits, paying export subsidies for the products of those industries sent abroad, sometimes even prohibiting the importation of products from other countries, etc. It is «the artificial means of creating manufacturers, of expropriating independent workers, of transforming the instruments and material conditions of labor into capital, of forcibly accelerating the transition from the traditional system of production to the modern system» (Chapter XXXI).

Primitive accumulation and the genesis of the industrial capitalist thus derive their strength from public debt and taxation, from the colonial system, from banking finance, and from protectionism. Sometimes governments lent capital directly to manufacturers. All these phenomena loomed large at the dawn of large-scale industry. It also benefited unrestrainedly from the rounding up of children, a veritable slave trade in little whites, parallel to that of black slavery. With the Peace of Utrecht, England reserved for itself the privilege of the slave trade between Africa and Spanish America; from this trade came the greatness of Liverpool: «for this orthodox city, the traffic in human flesh was the specific method of primitive accumulation». «This is the price we paid for our conquests, this is what it took to develop the eternal and natural laws of capitalist production, to consummate the divorce of the worker from his working conditions, to transform these into capital and the mass of the people into wage earners, into working poor». «If, as Augier says, money comes into the world with a thirst for blood on its lips, capital oozes blood and mud from every pore”.


51. The modern theory of colonization

(This chapter XXXIII is preceded by XXXII, which we will summarize later, given its conclusive and programmatic nature).

The economic situation created by capitalism in the colonies of the first occupations is very interesting—apart from a complete study of the phenomenon of imperialism—because it shows a flagrant contradiction in bourgeois economics. In defining private property as originating from labor, savings, and abstinence, bourgeois economics deliberately confuses private ownership of personal means of labor with capitalist ownership based on the labor of others. It suits the bourgeois economic theorist to apply to capitalist society the same concepts of law and the same definition of property inherited from a pre-capitalist society. We have seen all the absurdities of this way of looking at things. In the colonies, however, bourgeois economics itself is forced to admit and call for the violent destruction of small private property in order to make way for capitalist production.

After using the colonies as mere stores of accumulated treasure to be plundered, as places to buy goods needed in Europe, and above all as outlets for the manufactured goods of the mother country, capitalism naturally wanted to transport the same machines for producing surplus value, its industrial plants, to the colonies.

There was now no shortage of capital to purchase and transform the means of production and perhaps even raw materials and foodstuffs on the scene: all that was needed was wage labor. But the natives of the colonies either lived well on small-scale personal production or had previously been driven into the interior or even exterminated; it was therefore not easy to transform them into free wage laborers, as it had been easy to reduce them to slavery. As for the settlers who arrived from the mother country, they found before them immense expanses of unoccupied land to use for agriculture and often for mining. When free land exists, that is, when there is an unlimited supply of it, everyone obtains it almost free of charge and by right of occupation. Thus, the same “sacred and natural” law of supply and demand that forces the landless in Europe to sell their labor power gives them the opportunity in the colonies to easily obtain the means of labor for a free personal enterprise. Moreover, in the nascent farms there was not only agricultural and pastoral work, but also small domestic industries; the American farmer made his own tools, furniture, and even his own house. The willing capitalist, having no workers and no buyers, could even refrain from all consumption, as he would not have accumulated a penny of surplus value. The case of the distinguished Mr. Peel, who brought with him from England to America £50,000 worth of food and means of production, and was moreover so shrewd as to bring with him 3,000 members of the working class, including men, women, and children, is infinitely amusing. But not only did Mr. Peel fail to open any factories, he was cruelly abandoned by everyone, so that he was left without a servant to make his bed or draw water for him. «Unfortunate Peel, who had foreseen everything! He had only forgotten to export the English relations of production».

What do the theorists of the ‘naturalness’ of capitalism do? First of all, they defend slavery or forced labor of the indigenous people (a topic of debate in the League of Nations until after the First World War), caring little about kicking the law of free supply and demand in the teeth. And as for the white colonists, not daring to support slavery, they kick the law a second time by proposing that the state set a very high and artificial price for concessions of free land, so that immigrants, unable to buy it, will be forced to work as wage earners. The British government implemented this plan to promote capitalist accumulation in the colonies, but then the flow of emigrants turned towards the western United States, which until the end of the 19th century was insufficiently populated and rich in free land. However, after forcing bourgeois economists to disavow themselves, capitalist development rendered their panaceas useless.

Capitalist accumulation in America, since the Civil War of 1861, which produced enormous public debt, taxes, and the birth of the most vile financial aristocracy, reached dizzying heights through the World War and the period that followed. The United States, saturated with proletarians and threatened by massive unemployment, began to reject Asian and European immigrants. Inevitably having to dump huge masses of products overseas, and perhaps tomorrow, for reasons of internal politics, part of the plethoric industrial reserve army that is forming there, having arrived too late in the division of colonial domination, they will certainly attempt to colonize Europe itself, overturning its productive apparatus and thus provoking a new and greater conflict. (We leave this concluding passage unchanged in the form contained in the draft of this summary, prepared by some comrades in Ponza in 1929 – Editor’s note).





CONCLUSION


52. The historical outcome of capitalist accumulation

We have seen that what characterizes primitive accumulation, i.e., the historical formation of capitalism, is the expropriation of the immediate producer, i.e., the producer who possesses enough means of production to enable him to carry out his personal work and remain the owner of the products, which he will exchange to obtain what he needs.

Even in this form, it is private property, but it is wrong to say that the small producer owns capital. Capitalist private property only exists when the means of production and the products belong to non-workers, and the actual workers have been expropriated. We therefore have two distinct types of private property: private property of the worker (artisan and peasant era), private property of the non-worker (capitalist era).

The worker’s private ownership of the means of his productive activity corresponds to small-scale production, i.e., small agricultural or manufacturing enterprises in which the workforce, in addition to the free worker, includes his family and at most a few apprentices. This stage of production is primitive, but it has its justification in the course of technical development. Its replacement of prehistoric collective property, in which the almost immediate products of nature were exploited with a minimum of work and procedures, is justified. The small business system «is the nursery of social production, the school where manual skill, ingenious dexterity, and the free individuality of the worker are developed».

This type of technology and enterprise can accompany different legal forms of property and different types of society: it is found in slavery (alongside the private ownership of the non-worker over the land, the worker’s own person, and the product) and in the feudal system (alongside private land ownership and serfdom), but its true form accompanies that type of production in which the worker is the free owner of the conditions of work, i.e., the farmer of the land, the craftsman of the tool. This system of small independent producers presupposes the fragmentation of the land and the scattering of other means of production. After having rendered its services, if it were to continue, it would become a force opposing further development, which takes the form of the concentration of the means of production, with the most modern resources such as the collaboration of a large number of industries, the division of labor, and machinery, everything that makes it possible to push to the maximum the «wise domination of man over nature, the free development of the social powers of labor, agreement and unity in the ends, means, and efforts of collective activity».

The organization of small-scale production therefore becomes at a certain point incompatible with the new forces aroused by the new technical possibilities and necessities within society. It must be eliminated in order to allow the transformation of scattered means of production into concentrated means of production. But the next stage is still a stage of private property: a social class will take advantage of the inevitable concentration of private property to make it its monopoly and base its rule on it. The realization of all this constitutes the primitive accumulation and the consequent violent and cruel expropriation of the working people, the atrocity of which we have pointed out. It is in the midst of a real social tragedy that private property based on personal labor is replaced by capitalist property; that the final divorce between labor and property takes place. This expropriating tragedy forms the prehistory of Capital.

This transition is, for us, that is, for the results of our scientific investigation of the interplay of economic forces and the historical development of society, entirely inevitable; moreover, it is an indispensable condition for the useful development of human productive force and technique. Its development is therefore revolutionary, and if, by some absurd hypothesis, it depended on our approval and that of a supposed “moral conscience”, we should not deny it. In announcing its atrocity, we have not contradicted ourselves at all, but have exposed and demolished the tendentious apologetic theories of capitalist property which, in claiming to prove its eternity, are not content with highlighting the historical necessity of its appearance and its contribution to the liberation of further bursting productive forces, but want to present its formation as peaceful, idyllic, beneficial, and pleasant to the very masses of humanity involved in the relentless machinery of that process.

As for our method, moral judgments have no place in it, especially when it comes to establishing the objective laws of social development. We will deal with them for the purpose of destroying erroneous ideologies and when it comes to resolving the problem of the conscious and voluntary intervention of human collectivities (parties) in the stages of development. For even then, what determines the program will not be provided by moral evaluations. As far as the investigation is concerned, we carry it out using a method that is common to all modern natural sciences, which excludes the sentimental judgments of the observer. When we ask the observer to tell us whether and to what extent oxygen promotes life and carbon dioxide destroys it, we are not interested in whether one fact or the other pleases or displeases him. Having positively established that capitalism had to destroy the multitudes of small producers in order to achieve productive concentration, we accept this fact. What we cannot accept, even scientifically, is the capitalist claim to have brought delight and well-being to those multitudes by merely cutting off the heads of a few despots and lords. This assertion conflicts more with the facts than with moral assumptions; while it serves to establish how low the moral assumptions of bourgeois thought and all other thought are.


53. What will be the further development of capitalism

We have thus sought and exposed the laws of the functioning of capitalist production and those of its historical formation. But what will be its further development?

It cannot be objected that asking this question goes beyond the strictly scientific method: all sciences, after having posed the problem of the functioning of the universe and its evolutionary process in the past, pose that of its future development; we are therefore consistent in doing the same for the science of human society.

In resolving the question of what will become of the social form of capitalist private property, we do not start from a preconceived moral or finalistic process, such as the indefinite perfectibility of man, Progress, the triumph of Justice, Equality, and Freedom. Such words, taken by themselves, mean nothing to us, knowing full well that their value varies according to the times and classes.

First of all, we base ourselves on the path already traveled by society in order to recognize the actual laws of development. Furthermore, our hypothesis that production technology tends to become increasingly efficient and complex, and results in an ever-improving organization of humanity’s struggle against the difficulties of the natural environment, is not for us a mysterious and absolute truth, nor an uncontrollable intention or an irresistible aspiration of our feelings. It is a scientific conclusion with a high degree of probability, both because the historical data confirm it and because the biological laws of adaptability to the environment and the evolution of species lead to it. If we have called it only a hypothesis, it is to dispel any residual mystical or idealistic interpretation, and because the events of man’s struggle against nature could be slowly or even abruptly reversed by physical facts against which human society would be powerless, such as a change in temperature, humidity, atmospheric composition, a collision of stars, etc., facts which are, however, highly unlikely. Social factors could also reverse the direction of development, such as a chemical war that permanently poisoned various layers of the Earth’s atmosphere or something similar (10). Assuming, however, that such unforeseen events do not occur, we can rely on the certainty of productive progress, the increasing complexity of technology, and with it human activities and needs. Our conclusion, therefore, on the further advance of human efforts against natural difficulties does not need to be supported by flights of fancy or idealistic a priori assumptions, nor by faith in a mission of human intelligence (and even less in superhuman intelligence), without which the world would become useless and impossible!

Let us therefore resume the process of social transformation. With the old society of small enterprises thoroughly decomposed, the producers transformed into proletarians and their working conditions into capital, the socialization of labor and the further transformation of the soil and other means of production into socially managed instruments are constantly advancing.

We see this concentration continuing before our very eyes, thanks once again to expropriation. It is no longer the small producer who is expropriated, but the smaller capitalists who are expropriated by the larger ones. The small enterprise of the past has disappeared, but the new collective enterprises are always too small in relation to the resources of technology and give way to new, more perfect and larger enterprises. The application of science to technical means is developing in ever-increasing proportions, in the sense of ever greater interconnection between the various centers of production, between the various spheres of activity, between the various countries of the world. Machinery, telegraphy and radiotelegraphy, railways, navigation, aviation, etc., make it technically and increasingly necessary to solve production problems on a global rather than just a national scale. Technical improvement was once hindered by the small size of companies, but today it is hindered by their private autonomy, even if they are large and powerful companies. Development was once hampered by personal private property, but today it is once again hampered by capitalist private property.


54. New contrast between productive forces and forms of property - The proletarian revolution

The new needs arising within capitalism create new situations for the social classes and thus develop new forces that are poorly restrained by the legal forms of property implemented by capitalist power on the ruins of previous social and state regimes.

«As the number of capital magnates who usurp and monopolize all the advantages of this process of social transformation decreases, the mass of misery (11), oppression, slavery, degradation, and exploitation grows, but so does the rebellion of the working class, which is growing ever larger and is disciplined, united, and organized by the same mechanism of the capitalist production process». Small producers lived in isolation and were economic rivals of one another. The capitalists themselves, even though they stand together at the head of society, are implacable competitors with one another. They are right in saying that competition is the indispensable spring of production; they should only add: of production on a capitalist basis. It is therefore difficult for capitalists to dispense with competition and identify their social interests on a world scale. But the proletarians live in large masses; the bourgeois revolution has made them free, that is, it has forced them to run from country to country and from continent to continent in search of work, and competition among them is clearly to the detriment of all. The material conditions of this class (and not some mystical motive) give rise to a sense of solidarity and association on an ever-widening basis. It is not a moral imperative or the cry of an apostle, but the direct result of the forces set in motion by capitalism, which forms the real impulse behind the programmatic cry: “Proletarians of all countries, unite!”

«The monopoly of capital becomes a fetter on the mode of production which has developed with it and under it. The centralization of the means of production and the socialization of labor reach a point where their capitalist shell can no longer contain them. It is bursting. The death knell of capitalist private property has sounded. The expropriators are being expropriated».

The work of the mature Marx, a cold, descriptive, external critique of the economic world, ends with a cry that is an invitation to social war, a sure prerequisite for revolutionary victory.

What is the economic aspect of this new revolutionary conflict between the productive forces and the forms of property? It is this: the general technical-productive movement continues in the direction of the socialization of labor and the centralization of its material means. The expropriation of smaller private owners also continues, and, going beyond all limits, no private property is any longer compatible with the requirements of the new, vast social structure of productive activity. A transition must take place. Capitalist property and the formation of surplus value that characterizes it had to arise to make the beginning of socialization possible, but they must disappear for it to continue. However, this will certainly not be a reversal of the process that has already taken place; there will not be a counter-revolution but another revolution in economic relations.

The worker was deprived of his personal means of labor and will no longer become its isolated owner. However, the reunification of the worker with his working conditions will take place in the only way compatible with the transformations of technology, that is, the working community will acquire control and management of the whole of the means of production and the whole of the products.

«The capitalist form of appropriation arising from the capitalist system of production, and therefore capitalist private property, is the first negation of individual private property, which was based on personal labor. But capitalist production, with the necessity of a natural process, generates its own negation. It is the negation of the negation. It reestablishes not the private property of the worker, but ‘individual’ property on the basis of the acquisitions brought about by the capitalist era: that is, on the basis of collective labor and the common possession of the land and the means of production created by labor itself».

This penultimate paragraph of the work recalls the classic expressions of dialectics and links to what Marx writes in the second preface, in 1873, about Hegelian dialectics, whose mystifying aspect (not mystical, translators!) he claims to have been criticizing for thirty years, while acknowledging that Hegel was the first to expound the dialectical method. Marx turned this upside down; in Hegel, the process of thought stood on its head and created reality; in Marx, on the contrary, «it is nothing but the material transported and translated into the human head». A short appendix to this work will be published on this point under the title “Marx’s dialectical method”.

It is clear that the expression “individual” property, referring to the negation of its negation, that is, to the collectivist system of distribution that succeeds capitalism, means that each participant in social production will be able to participate in the enjoyment of social products without any force or right of private usurpation interposing itself, as the independent producer already did in his small private circle for the products of his personal labor.

And Capital closes with a reference to the passage in the Manifesto concerning the revolutionary function of the proletariat, because with this connection the author wanted to reaffirm the constructive continuity of his doctrine from the statements of 1847 to the completion of his monumental work.

This is a shining example that will endure in the history of the movement against the repeated and tireless attacks of lies, deception, and betrayal.

«The unstoppable progress of industry, of which the bourgeoisie is the unwitting agent, replaces the isolation of workers born of competition with their revolutionary union through association. As large-scale industry develops, the very basis on which the bourgeoisie has established its production slips away from under its feet.

«The bourgeoisie therefore produces, in advance, its own gravediggers. Its downfall and the triumph of the proletariat are equally inevitable».






NOTES:

(1) - It is of particular importance to deal with measurable quantitative magnitudes in scientific research. The aim of all science is the organic exposition of a given group of facts or phenomena acquired by our experience, in such a way as to highlight the relationships which constantly run between the facts themselves. The scientific experience of this relationship is called law. The most complete and satisfactory form of a scientific law is that of a relationship between measurable quantities (mathematical formula). For quantities to be measurable it is necessary to be able to refer them to other quantities already known, and in this reference lies the law itself. Example: you know how to measure space (length) in meters, time in seconds, you measure speed taking as a unit that of a meter in a second, and apply the law speed = space / time.

Some laws translate relations, corresponding to experience, between quantities already all known, we have then a real new discovery; others, like that given in example, are reduced to introducing deductively a new quantity, and have value of theoretical conventions; however the application to phenomena of their logical consequences will decide their validity or not. Therefore not all conventions, which define quantities by giving the way to measure them and to refer them to others, are arbitrarily possible, but, even if first assumed as hypotheses, they are finally either confirmed or rejected by the application to experimental facts. So for example with the atomic hypothesis the notion of the quantity “atomic weight” was introduced and while for a long time it was thought to be an expedient of convenience to make the chemical formulae square, further studies on experimental data allowed to ascertain the real existence of atoms and to determine their weight both absolute and relative to that of hydrogen unity.

Anticipating a conclusion that may be part of research on the “theory of knowledge” in the Marxist system, we also note that treating the entities investigated with numerical measures and mathematical relations between their quantitative measures leads to making the notions and relations and their possession and handling less individual, more impersonal and collectively valid. The pure qualitative appreciation contained in judgments and investigations communicated in words of common language, retains the personal imprint because the words and their relationships take on a different value from man to man according to previous tendencies and material emotional and cognitive predispositions. Therefore, all judgments and moral, aesthetic, religious, philosophical and political principles communicated and disseminated verbally and in writing are personal and subjective. The systems of figures and relationships of mathematical symbols (algorithms) with which even many people who claim to be educated are unfamiliar, tend to establish results that are valid for all researchers, or at least transferable to broader fields without being easily distorted by particular interpretations.

The transition, in the history of society and its knowledge, is certainly not simple; it is hard and difficult and not without returns and errors, but in this sense the modern scientific method is constituted.

Of great interest for this purpose, and in order to give a real and material objective value to human knowledge, will be the examination of modern “algorithms” that have reached such power to work and walk “on their own” in a certain sense outside of consciousness and intelligence, and as real “machines” for knowledge. Their science becomes no longer a fact of the ego, but a social fact. The theoretical “I”, like the economic and juridical “I”, must be broken!

Marx wanted to treat with scientific method even human economic facts, similarly to what science and bourgeois philosophy had done for the phenomena of physical nature.

He did not simply use an algorithm because he thought and worked, he exposed and fought at the same time; and in addition to the weapons of the new era, he had to and knew how to use those with which the enemy resisted: polemics, eloquence, invective and sarcasm, under which he prostrated his contradictors many times.

It is in the din of this battle that the new science of society and history was built.

Now we have to overcome a first point: to make a science of value, whether the ideological and philosophical economists like it or not, it is necessary to introduce a measure, just as Galileo and Newton were able to make science of gravity by measuring masses, accelerations and forces. The fruitfulness of the new method – while giving solutions susceptible to future more grandiose developments, and not leading to “true absolutes” alien to science – routed and buried forever the wrong approaches of the past on these problems.


(2) - The titles in the original work are: The production of absolute surplus-value for Part III and The production of relative surplus-value for Part IV.

We make more use of simple mathematical formulas than the original. Sure enough, this is not just a matter of allowing Marx’s theses to be grasped with less effort, but above all of re‑establishing their exact meaning in a way that falsifiers and adversaries find impossible to contest. In the text, great skill is required to arrive at a good understanding when models of the phenomenon – of necessity theoretical – are subject to scientific treatment, and when it comes to broad historical-narrative expositions.

(3) - The entirety of this first enunciation of the formation of surplus-value in Marx’s work is flanked and enlivened by an evocative description of the relation between boss and worker, through a polemic with official bourgeois economics and with the vacuous ethical and juridical concepts which underlie the present institutions, or rather the apologetics of them. Marx points out, step by step, which of his findings and postulates are held to be self‑evident in the admissions of ordinary economists, and where lie the pitfalls and tricks which lead them to avoid his rigorous and scientific conclusions, out of the prejudice and interest of school and class.

In his historical references Marx underlines with incomparable effectiveness the theses, which we will encounter again later and which are essential to Marxism, that the extortion of surplus-value has not existed in all social epochs, since it was lacking in primitive communities, such as in the autonomous individual and familial production of the small artisan and of the peasant smallholder as long as the latter remained free, that is to say, not subject to tithes and corvée. In contrast, it comes into being in various forms with slavery, feudal serfdom, and wage labor. This lays the groundwork for the demonstration that the fact of surplus-labor and surplus-value, and therefore of exploitation, far from being inseparable from every kind of economy, as the bourgeois theorist pretends, can and will disappear in the future economy.

In a brilliant critique of the ethical-juridical kind, in which the author dialectically and subtly pretends to take seriously the moral norms of bourgeois philosophy and those of modern law, reducing them to absurdity and ridiculousness, we are shown the perfect legal, ethical, and Christian fairness of everything that takes place on the market, with exchanges in which everyone sells at a fair price what is rightfully his, and at last, the “fraud” hidden in the secret of the productive process is revealed.

To set the foundation for the judgment on the philosophical, religious, moral and political superstructures of the capitalist world, it is pointed out in powerful passages that there are two conditions for the “game” of the appropriation of surplus-value to be possible every time the capitalist comes into contact with the worker, and for it to be applied on an ever larger scale in the historical process.

They consist in the freedom of the worker, in a double sense. First, he must be free to alienate his own labor power, and therefore the new jurisprudence (whereby all citizens are equal before the law) must break the feudal serfdom which bound men to the land, and the guild system which bound them to the trade and shop. Second, he must be freed from every hindrance of possessing on his own account instruments of labor and small supplies of raw materials, as he did when he was an artisan or a peasant. This is accomplished through the initial expropriation of small producers, from which capitalism was ferociously born.

At the same time we are shown that this process, however infamous, was needed to bring about the more intense and higher-yield forms of production necessitated by modern technological means. But the whole mastery of these descriptive and critical fundamentals of the current mode of production, and of the path by which it has been realized, serves as a basis for the thesis that its dynamic aspects, such as the application of scientific discoveries and machinery, and the principle of the associated and co‑ordinated labor of an ever larger number of producers, are not separable from the extortion of surplus-value and the monopoly of the means of production and exchange held by the capitalist class.

The study of Marx’s work and its use as an argument and means of propaganda and of class and party struggle can be made after having mastered the central line of investigation and deduction of which we have tried to present the outline, perhaps dry but clear, and then by following the development of Marx’s “narration”, stopping at all those seeming digressions which, despite appearing as such, in reality represent syntheses and anticipations of the programmatic and political positions of the communists.

This gives the lie to the idiotic assumption that the true “spirit” of Marxism is a cold description of the economic phenomena of today’s social world, carefully eschewing the risk of forecasting and proposing its overthrow.

(4) - Do not find this succession of little formulas too dry. It is intended as a demonstration of the validity of the general law of surplus-value given by Marx, illustrated using economic enterprises of the capitalist type.

We are here at the end of Part III, which establishes the definition of surplus-value. At the end of Part V and before proceeding to the treatment of the accumulation of capital, in a small summary chapter on the various formulas of surplus-value, Marx contrasts the two groups of formulas which characterize classical bourgeois economics and Marxist economics (Chap. XVI of the original text).

Both are based on the admission that value is given by labor. But they present the matter quite differently when it comes to answering the following question: what part of the working day does the worker work for himself, and what part does he work for the owner of the company?

In both cases we may speak of necessary labor for the first part, which is that which is paid in full, and of surplus-labor for the second part (of labor time), which is the part whose equivalent goes to form the profit of the company owner.

According to the bourgeois economist, the formulas are:

Surplus-labor
Necessary labor
 =  Surplus-value
Cost of the product

In other words, that ratio reproduces what capitalist accounting calls the rate of profit, earnings, dividend, and so on. We find the same fraction by writing in the numerator the profit margin on a given production output, that is, the excess of the realized price over the total cost, and in the denominator this same cost.

If a car, let us say, costs – between materials, wages, wear and tear, machinery, etc., etc. – one hundred thousand, and is sold for 110,000, the company earns 10%. It is then claimed that the worker has only been exploited for 10% of his labor time. If he has worked 11 hours, he has recovered the full proceeds of ten, and only for one hour has he worked for the capitalist.

Modern official economics, with its pretensions to positive exactitude, always follow this thesis, and therefore rejects Marx’s theory of surplus-value, treating it as a brilliant polemical exercise and not as science.

In the latter, however, the formulas take a very different turn and look as follows (starting from the same initial ratio):

Surplus-labor
Necessary labor
 =  Surplus-value
Variable capital
 =  Surplus-value
Wages

The degree of exploitation, i.e., the amount of unpaid labor, is not put in relation to the whole expenditure, i.e., to the whole advanced capital, but to the wage expenditure alone, called by us the variable part of the total capital.

The difference between the two interpretations is enormous. Quantitatively, as Marx shows here and elsewhere, it implies that the rate of surplus-value is much higher. If in that car only twenty thousand, out of the hundred thousand, have been spent on wages, the rate rises from 10% to 50%, since it is now given by the ratio of the profit of 10,000 to the variable capital of 20,000. One‑third of the day is unpaid. There are examples, such as one taken from contemporary English agriculture, of rates of up to 300%.

Qualitatively, then, the formula of current economics lends itself to showing the relation between wage‑earner and capitalist as a form of free association, while the Marxist law shows its fundamental antagonistic character.

With our little calculation concerning the merger of two companies, we wished to show how establishing the quantitative relation between surplus-value and wage‑capital is not a whim of our economic school, but rather the only way of accounting for the phenomenon under study, since what in the single cycle appears as constant capital in the hands of the company owner is nothing but the accumulated product of previous wage‑capitals, which have given rise to other previous surplus-values from unpaid labor.

The subterfuge and tendentiousness are thus inherent to the very act – common as it may be – of presenting the balance sheets of productive enterprises (even non‑private ones), which are accepted as self‑evident and accurate by academic economics and bourgeois legality.

(5) - Since accumulated surplus-value becomes new capital, and surplus-value arises from capital invested in labor, there is a limit to accumulation given by the size of the working population, which tends to rise with the number of inhabitants of the earth; by the portion of the earth that has been pervaded by capitalist “civilization”; and by the ratio of proletarians to citizens due to the progressive expropriation of the middle classes.

But may it not seem that the enormous mass of constant capital, that is, capital consisting of plant and commodity (product) reserves, has in the modern world increased to an even more impressive extent than the mass of available working days? And does this not contradict the Marxist construction?

We certainly do not want to answer such a question now, since we must first expound and understand the whole doctrine of accumulation (Part VII), and further still, the doctrine of the Marxist school on imperialism. But it is interesting to consider how a “conservative” solution, namely that which prolongs the duration of the capitalist cycle, consists in the “destruction” of the constant capital produced, that is, of plant and stockpiles, and in the reduction of countries that are already rich and advanced in the industrial sense to “unequipped” countries by the devastation of their installations (factories, railways, ships, machinery, buildings of all kinds, etc.).

Thus the reconstitution of that enormous mass of dead capital allows for a further mad rush to invest in variable capital, that is, in living, exploited human labor.

Wars effectuate this elimination of installations and commodity stockpiles, whereas the destruction of laboring hands does not reach the same proportion owing to the increase in population of the prolific human animal.

In the very civilized reconstruction (the biggest deal of the century, for the bourgeois: an even more criminal aspect of capitalist barbarism than wartime destruction itself, for us, disciples of Marx), it then sustains itself on the insatiable creation of new surplus-value.

(6) - We have preferred the word ‘collaboration’ to the Italian word ‘cooperazione’, which could lead to a misunderstanding with the cooperative production organisations – a rather secondary phenomena in the midst of the countless private capitalist companies – in the hope that there will be no further misunderstanding with the meaning of the well-known expression of class collaboration.

(7) - We have alluded here to the problems of determinism and freedom of initiative, to be dealt with in the study on the theoretical-philosophical part of Marxism, and those on the function and tactics of the Party, dealt with in theses and texts of a political nature.

(8) - The enormous social possibilities offered by the use of atomic energy, after the various forms of natural, thermal, and mechanical energy, are inevitably captured by capitalist accumulation, under the forms of ruthless control and monopoly that lead to the enslavement and dehumanization of the physical discoverer and experimenter, as well as of all those who work in the new field.

(9) - Suffice it to say that the Second World War accentuated its economic consequences not only in the destruction caused by military operations extending far beyond the battlefronts, but also in the systematic dismantling of the industrial infrastructure of the defeated and occupied countries. A new global race for re-accumulation thus began, a gigantic reserve army of starving people was formed, and this extreme form of barbarism was covered up with the apologetics of “reconstruction” that would have made Attila or Genghis Khan blush.

(10) - Up to the date of the first draft (1929). Today, the possible consequences of the use of atomic weapons must be added.

(11) - Translated literally, to correct the current versions: what grows is “die Masse des Elends” - the mass of misery - not the misery of the working class. The “free” translators do not understand that Marx would have contradicted himself if he had made the “degradation” and “organization” of the working class grow at the same rate. Of this disciplined (geschulten) vanguard of the oppressed and crushed masses, die Empörung (subject of the adversative proposition) grows, that is, not simple resistance, as we read in the Avanti! editions, but Rebellion.